b2o: boundary 2 online

Author: boundary2

  • Christian Thorne Interviews Oded Nir–Searching for the Universal in Israel/Palestine

    Christian Thorne Interviews Oded Nir–Searching for the Universal in Israel/Palestine

    Searching for the Universal in Israel/Palestine

    An Interview with Oded Nir

    Christian Thorne: You are on record as saying that you wished Marxists had more to say about Israel/Palestine. It is your sense, I think, that we would understand events better if we factored in the place of Israel in the world system; considered the requirements of capital in the region; and understood the configurations of class in the country, sometimes across the Israeli-Palestinian divide. Your writing sometimes gives the impression that most of the work on this front is still in front of us — that Marxist thinking about Israel/Palestine has mostly failed to appear. Can I ask you even so where you think we should start? What are Marxism’s most enduring insights into Israel/Palestine, going back to the 1940s or, if you prefer, to the 1880s? What, in particular, do Marxists have to add to the “settler colonial” paradigm, which is well represented in discussions of Israel, including in the Palestine solidarity movement in Europe and North America? The question, of course, will pop if I put it the other way round: What do we miss when we talk only about “settler colonialism”?

    Oded Nir: Yes, I do think that Marxism can add much to the way we understand Israel/Palestine, not just in adding another dimension to it, but in fundamentally defining the horizon of a political commitment to Palestinian liberation in particular, and its relationship to global struggles for emancipation more generally. And I want to say right from the start that what I have to say won’t solve any problems, but just modify how we perceive these problems.

    Let’s get straight to the heart of the disagreement between the settler colonialism paradigm and Marxism. One would think that the difference between a Marxist and a non-Marxist leftist position would be in the answer to this question: does capitalism drive horrible oppression and cruelty? Or is capitalist exploitation just a secondary dimension, one area  among others where colonial oppression is expressed? Unfortunately, much of the writing on Palestine/Israel that touches on economic issues falls on one of these sides, or on a third option: not choosing at all, seeing a little bit of both at work.

    But this way of posing the problem should be rejected, since it allows us to provide only bad solutions to it: if we say capitalism is the driver of Palestinian oppression, we are in danger of reducing colonial violence to a side effect of capitalist development; and if we think that (colonial) abuse of power is behind everything, we are in danger of falling into a flat moralism, into seeing ourselves as choosing what is righteous, while others choose evil. The problem here is that the wrong life cannot be lived rightly, as Adorno puts it: flat moralizing fails to take into account the way we are, materially, part of the bad world, and the way it exerts pressures on what we (and others) can and cannot do.

    To head off one objection: I’m not preaching cynicism here–Adorno didn’t mean we should just shrug off suffering, because life is bad anyway. I think we must remain sensitive to suffering, and fight for it to end. But it does mean that, unfortunately, given the wrongness of the world, any act in it is tainted with this wrongness, necessarily depends on it, and can lead to its reproduction: existing social forces make this result highly likely. So the horizon of any action must always also contain its own negation–weirdly, this means that I should act now in a way that aims to eliminate the possibility of this very act in future generations.

    So I have a weird and seemingly non-Marxist way to proceed from this: to say that Palestine/Israel today names not a scientific problem, not a problem to be solved by study and rigorous analysis, but a problem of narrative and of ideology. The debate between settler-colonialism and Marxism is a debate between two kinds of materialism, two ways of understanding material forces at work. In this debate, materialism is the only game in town. And the dominance of materialism is not limited to activists and “radical” thinkers: mainstream media today is full of analyses of material power relations. So, to my mind, the really excluded possibility is that of materialism’s opposite, which we used to call idealism. There is a great tradition–one that includes figures such as Mao, Mahdi Amel, and Fredric Jameson–that insists that Marxism is not a set of positive statements or a stable methodology; Marxism, rather, has to be reinvented in new historical situations–to do the same thing, you have to do something different. I think that today, when materialism is itself a dominant ideology, Marxism has to take up the opposite pole, to have an uncompromising idealist kernel. This way—and only this way—will it take on a position that is truly repressed almost everywhere.

    And I would say that what idealism comes down to, in this case, is narrative. You mention previous Marxist positions on Palestine/Israel and their enduring insights. So I want to briefly say how some of these were transformative, not in their contributions to knowledge, which were undoubtedly significant, but in the way they completely reconfigured how one understood the condition and aims of emancipatory struggle. One example that I like, from Jewish-Israeli circles, took place in the 1970s and ‘80s, around the coming into being of Matzpen (a group that broke off from the Israeli communist party) and, say, Tamar Gozansky’s The Development of Capitalism in Palestine, which came out in the mid-1980s, right before the wave of what is known as Post-Zionism. The situation of socialist struggle in Israel at that point was not very good: it had been completely neutralized by state institutions that, at least until the late 1970s, promoted a calcified and toothless version of the discourse of class struggle. And so what the communist interventions of Matzpen and Gozansky did, was to discover class antagonism anew, precisely by mediating it through the analyses of the British-colonial, Zionist, and later Israeli oppression of Palestinians.

    In its moment, this was a monumental shift, one that not only reinvented Israeli socialism, but later became a way to revitalize the entire Israeli left. So we saw the birth of the 1990s peace process, which was the name for an   entire utopian program, of which what we know as Post Zionism was merely the intellectual wing. What is important for me is to emphasize that this was a shift in narrative and ideology–the coming into being of a new language through which to imagine a (contradictory or self-negating) path to liberation.

    Thorne: Your framing the issue in terms of narrative raises all sorts of fresh considerations. Can you summarize us for that older story about class, the one that was dominant when the Labor Party enjoyed a near monopoly on power in Israel? And can you help us see how the story told by Matzpen and Tamar Gozansky was different?

    Nir: To answer this question, I think it would be best to turn to literature. I’m thinking in particular about the genre called Zionist realism that flourished in the early 20th century, and that is today usually mocked by critics for being mere propaganda. There is one short story that narrates the experiences of a Jewish immigrant to Palestine, who joins a group of other Jews in working the land for a Jewish land owner. The worker, who isn’t accustomed to physical labor, is in a state of excitement throughout the story: he sees every physical chore he completes as part of a historical Act, a form of direct participation in the making of a new Jewish history. But as the story progresses, you hear that the Jewish workers are competing with much more skilled Palestinian labor: our character sees Palestinian workers being driven off the land in the beginning, and they emerge marginally throughout the story in his thoughts.

    But the story ends when the job is complete, at which point the Jewish workers are themselves driven off the land, and the narrator is completely shocked: his sense of being inseparable from history-in-the-making, from working the land, completely crumbles. This of course recalls the Palestinian workers who had already been driven away. There’s no “moral” to the story–it ends with the workers’ separation from the product of their work.

    What I like about this very simple allegory is that it is able to hold together what are radically incompatible meanings: on the one hand, the revolutionary kernel of early Zionism, the attempt to make history within given conditions; on the other, the betrayal, uncompromisingly rendered, of this very attempt: intentional history-making turns into unintentional history-making; existing conditions turn your emancipatory intention not only against the Palestinian other, whom you have left out, but also against your own liberation.

    This is the tragedy of the Labor Party in a nutshell, one that was much better recorded and conceptualized in literature than in actual political discussions: the story I’ve mentioned captured this process as it’ was taking place. It is the turning of the code of class antagonism from holding a revolutionary truth, one that potentially leads to a radically different world, into a hegemonic ideology, one that is used to oppress both Palestinians and Jews. For us, it’s clear which side won. But in the moment, one completely loses the feeling of history-in-the-making if one doesn’t acknowledge the potential for social transformation, the possibility of making something new–the utopian impulse that these workers embody, the deep undecidability that makes that moment ripe for intervention. This is exactly why Israeli socialists in the 1970s found themselves without a language: class discourse had become a tool of oppression, a code through which Israelis gained entry to the dominant classes! This is what the Labor Party had devolved to, since 1948.

    This was the background to the interventions of Matzpen and later Gozansky. It is as if someone–the state–stole the language through which you can express the fact of oppression. On the one hand, you have class antagonism in Israel without a symbolic code in which to express it. On the other hand, there are those completely excluded from the hegemonic code: Palestinians, and Mizrahi Jews, discriminated against by the Jewish-European hegemony. What Matzpen and Gozansky did may seem simple and obvious to us, but it was not so obvious at the time: to affirm symbolically the oppression of these excluded groups and the need to fight it. It’s important to mention that reversing this exclusion is not an easy thing to do in practice. This is where ideas about uneven development are important: when one considers that such exclusions are what makes capitalist social relations possible–that in the context of Israel in the 1970s, the oppression of Palestinians, Mizrahi Jews, women, and LGBTQ+ were not accidental, but a necessary part of the capitalist structure—then you see how radical such demands can be: they threaten to undo capitalism as a whole, and radically transform how society is structured.

    This is what made the interventions by Matzpen and later Gozansky so important. Not only were the struggles they helped conceptualize important and righteous in their own right; they were the basis for a new universal struggle, a new way through which to come together to–potentially–transform the structure of the whole of society. At the end, of course, that didn’t happen. But that the potential for radical transformation was there should not be overlooked. One of the most important tasks is to see how and why these revolutionary efforts failed: this is a crucial part of re-narrating our present historically.

    Thorne: I’m interested in the phrase “new universal struggle.” You’ve written elsewhere that the history of Zionist and Israeli Marxism can be tracked by its serially transformed understandings of the universal. So let’s say that socialism is a universalist politics, but that any such politics can’t help but pass through the particular. A universalism comes into the world only when it is demanded by particular groups and housed in particular institutions. And in that case, the question becomes: Which particularities do we think can demand the universal most plausibly and realize it most amply? And your sense is that Zionist and Israeli Marxism has proposed over time different candidates for this role, different particulars to serve as bearer of the universal: first, the Israeli nation broadly; then, the Israeli working class more specifically; finally, as of the 1980s, the Palestinians as the excluded term. Am I hearing you right? If I am, I’m wondering what you think the status of the universal is now? Are the Palestinians still the bearer of the universal in the region? Gozansky’s work, after all, dates back to the 1980s and would seem to belong to the moment of the peace process and post-Zionism. But if the peace process is itself now a historical artifact, its very failure decades in the past, then what has been the fate of that particular universalism?

    Nir: Yes, I think that’s completely right: universal struggle is often mediated by what is a particular struggle, and that is something many current defenders of universality take up. The recent example of Black Lives Matter is a case in point: it mediated universality, while seeming particular; the “all lives matter” response to it from the Right was the truly particular, exclusionary, position, even if it seems universal at first sight.

    But things get more complicated once you realize that a particularity can be at one moment the historical mediator of universal change, but lose that universality in the next moment. This was true of the 1848 moment in the European bourgeois revolution–when the universal values turned from revolutionary weapon to an apology for the bourgeoisie’s social dominance. And it was equally true of Zionism’s failed revolution: from a particularism that had a universal aspect, it turned into an exclusionary, oppressive ideology. And I think the only other moment in Israeli history when a new universal-particularity came to be was that of the late 1970s and early ‘80s that I have been describing, in which the excluded Palestinians became the particular bearer of a potential universal transformation.

    But there are always false starts and wrong times that complicate the picture. In 1948, after the formal establishment of the state of Israel, one of the Zionist leaders surprisingly quit his post and joined a socialist party that insisted, against state leadership, that class struggle must still be waged in the newly established state, against its new authorities. That position unfortunately failed to become a significant political force. Efforts to create Zionist-Palestinian cooperation were almost nonexistent at that time: such efforts had become too fraught and were considered impossible. There is no point in criticizing such impossibility: for instance, socialism in the US was for many years an unthinkable option, even if there was no logical impossibility. In 1948, the sense that Zionism had ceased being an emancipatory ideology, that it was rapidly becoming a repressive ideology, had all kinds of similar effects: some prominent figures in the labor movement suddenly turned to the extreme Right, to Jewish ultra-nationalism. This was a response to the same historical dilemma, the same reification of Zionism into the opposite of liberation.

    The problem of false starts is interesting in several respects. It is easy to see the 1970s and ‘80s in Israel as a moment of formation of a new universal struggle, because we immediately recognize the demand for Palestinian liberation as a just one. But being morally right is not a historical criterion. False starts demonstrate that the political success of universality-in-particularity is not evident in the moment that it is first asserted. It is only from a later perspective that we can narrate it as such. And one can go a step further, and argue that it is the future that causes it to be universal, in a strong sense: it’s not only that we don’t know in advance which position will be successful, it’s that the possibility of narrating its success or failure is determined by the future.

    Such future causation is a result of how we think of the excluded particular. In any notion of universality that isn’t bloodless, the effort to include the excluded isn’t just a matter of busting down an arbitrary fence, of allowing someone, some group, to take part in a system that otherwise remains the same. No: what makes the inclusion of such particulars a universal demand is that including them would require a radical transformation of the social whole into which it is to be included, down to its basic structure.

    So false starts are important because they help us see, I think, that voluntarism or contingency are not the opposites of historical determination or causality, but necessary parts of it. To remain uncompromisingly loyal to subjective agency, to our freedom to act and respond in a way not determined in advance by circumstances, we must acknowledge that such contingency is only authentic if it eventually disappears: the future dissolves it into necessity and determination, into the necessary condition for the moment in which we live; or, if it fails to produce change, into something completely extraneous to the current moment. This is for me what false starts demonstrate.

    To come back to our moment: if you see, as I do, our moment as one of radical and unavoidable transition, then ethics, or belief, shimmer and come to the fore. No amount of fact checking or archival work or algorithmic position-play can take the place of the purely subjective intervention that we need–precisely because only the future can tell a false start from the successful universal struggle. Truth now is a matter of acting on one’s belief, in the strongest sense there is. This is also what makes this moment so anxiety-inducing, at least for me: no received wisdom–no matter how righteous–can save us from the need to decide and act. And, of course, I’m not saying that we shouldn’t take facts into consideration, that we shouldn’t learn from the past or that we should be purely impulsive. But I am saying that subjective intervention, one whose meaning is not decided in advance, is unavoidable. And that’s scary: are we wrong? Are we doing the right thing? Nothing can settle that question for now, even if it will eventually have an answer.

    The same thing holds in the case of Palestine/Israel. There are multiple contexts here, each requiring a different intervention. I already posed the question of what narrative work the Palestinian struggle does for us, here in the US–that’s one important context for intervention. It is not for me to talk about the internal Palestinian context, but it plainly requires careful attention. In Israel, it is clear that the Palestinian cause does not function, in Israel, as it did in the 1980s, as a particularity mediating universal struggle. I think we need in this context to distinguish between two positions that used to be fused together: one has to do with Israeli-Palestinian peace, collaboration and reconciliation; the other has to do with uncompromising support for Palestinian liberation, at all costs. While the latter has become the banner of some on the left, the former has virtually disappeared: the very word “peace” projects powerlessness, naiveté, and incoherence; it seems irrevocably nostalgic, a fool’s errand. Palestinian/Israeli collaboration is very strained, becoming almost impossible (this is affecting academic collaborations, too). There is a strong impulse to separate activists and intellectuals into different groups according to their nationality and ethnicity, in a manner that unfortunately comes close to a leftist version of symbolic segregation.

    If you see the situation this way, then, for me, the excluded particularity, what mediates universality, is the possibility of peace and collaboration. Yes, this is not an identity category, so it seems to violate the principle of particularity-mediating-universality. But one shouldn’t reify how particularity appears in the world. Sometimes, universality is mediated through … universality! Or at least through some more general term that becomes visible when you enlarge the field of vision. This is why I like to think about particularity in terms of items in a series, rather than only in terms of identity categories. Peace, or collaboration, can be such an excluded item. So, for me, this is the particular that right now mediates universality in Israel, and maybe in Palestine/Israel. Think about the initial gesture of the project of peacemaking in the 1980s-90s–it can be reduced to the statement: we are not pursuing Israeli-Palestinian peace effectively, we need to find a better way to pursue it. I think we need a similar gesture today: expressing support for the two-state solution has degenerated into ineffectual lip-service–it doesn’t promote any actual project of transformation. So how do we pursue peace more effectively? What are the institutions that we need to do it? What went wrong last time? All of these questions need to be answered, earnestly, with an eye to the reinvention of this project. One beginning of an answer, I think, is if we take peace to name a project that now mediates not only relations between two states, but within the state of Israel too: it has to be a class project, in addition to an ethnic-national project. It is closer to a one-state solution than to the two-state one. But I’m already getting here into details that belong elsewhere.

    Oded Nir is the author of Signatures of Struggle, a 2018 book on “the figuration of collectivity in Israeli fiction.” He has edited volumes on Marxist approaches to Israel/Palestine and on the literatures of the capitalist periphery. He teaches courses on Israeli culture and literature at Queens College.

  • Norman Klein–An Archeology of the 2024 US Elections

    Norman Klein–An Archeology of the 2024 US Elections

    An Archeology of the 2024 US Elections

    Norman Klein

    The United States is more than at a crossroads. It is in the midst of an interregnum that may last decades. Its constitution has been undermined. Rising inequality and oligarchy remain off the charts, despite the relative boom of the Biden years. The nation itself is dividing into three de facto countries: the Atlantic kingdom, the Pacific kingdom, and the new confederacy. All this suggests a long game, twenty or thirty years. Within that interregnum, any vast reorganization of digital capitalism, as part of fully dedicated master planning, will seem unworkable.

    Until the Harris campaign for president started, a collective morbidity in America seemed to guarantee a Trump victory. Then overnight, by a magical propulsion, the principle of solidarity took hold in the Democratic Party, even more than in 2008, and with a clarity of purpose not seen for eighty years. Once again, the change in wind patterns was dizzying. What might next month bring?

    Let us imagine there is a reversal of the feudal condition, of the stalemate that has seized the US by the throat (the gulf between the richest and poorest now resembles 1929, as if the twentieth century had never happened). I am astonished by the Democratic Party’s instant reversal, but not yet entirely impressed. One fact is sure: Trump will flame out, even if he succeeds in November. His MAGA sociopathic anti-plan is a suicide march, with no future and no greatness possible. Trump’s cult will flame out within two years, leaving a hole as deep as an asteroid. However, Trump is merely a caricature of something deep in the American character, echoing how the Atlantic settlements began after 1607: mercantilist, aristocratic charters slowly devolved into a partial democracy. However, along the way, the unfair pressures inspired many insurgencies; many vendettas larger than January 6. If Trump wins, a near collapse will linger, overwhelm America’s chances of any recovery for at least a decade. But even if he loses, many of the same challenges will need fixing anyway, or at least repair. For example: a need to fully restructure the American constitution; impose staggering election reforms immediately; then, but at the same time, rebuild the economic heartlands, while inventing a more egalitarian economic reality. All this requires very innovative master planning, especially of the infrastructure, as hurricanes, fires, and droughts continue to dash against it. Then last, but also first: America’s knowledge industries must be resculpted, not abandoned like an AI zombie land.

    If the Harris momentum crosses the victory line instead of Trump, that means a vast change in the American mood, because of this shared solidarity, even more than specific policies. But reversing America’s sour direction is not the same as solving crises that will clearly absorb decades. And I am saying if.

    The “new” American crisis began in 1973, with Nixon’s New Economic Program, which transfigured world financial policies and launched what became “globalization” by the eighties. But now, after the COVID-19 pandemic, those global supply chains are old. They have proven themselves unable to cope. Global capitalism pretends to be efficient, but is only relentless in its manic pursuit of profits at the speed of light. Global capitalism cannot, by itself, master plan on behalf of multinational needs. It “needs” instead a clearer partnership with governments. The US Federal Reserve and congress can provide the brakes and steering wheel that globalism requires—with its blind genius for just slamming into walls, adding to greedflation like a kleptocrat.

    And finally, world politics: addressing land wars from Ukraine to the Middle East. The unimaginable bloodshed resembles civil wars in Africa, but also the bloodlust of the seventeenth century, when religions and partisans seemed to be hyper-militarized by rage. That heating up of vengeance runs parallel to the heating up of the planet itself.

    All this points toward the major stumbling block: since the sixties, a contempt for the nation-state has grown in America, and has even been essential to politics from the far right to the far left. And yet, with COVID-19, as well as the Great Recession, the federal government, craven and corrupt, saved America from plummeting into pure nightmare, first in 2008. And with the waves of disaster out on the horizon, we realize that the nation-state has to get stronger. The problems are too large for any other approach. I look at this ruckus in support of Harris, this unexpected show of solidarity, and realize that it is also solidarity on behalf of the American federal government. The nation-state has become energized again. Indeed, the American election in November is all about restoring a viable path for expanding the nation-state, for regulating capital, for master planning against the perfect wave.

    Biden was an old-fashioned state-builder, an insider from the Senate who was also vice president, like Lyndon Johnson. His Senate finesse did show, along with his hubris–again vaguely like Johnson. But Johnson in 1968 was not threatening to dismantle the constitutional government itself. I was there as a New Lefty in 1968. No one in the antiwar insurgency truly wanted to tear down the nation-state to the bone, nor the constitution. I was, in fact, shocked, after participating in the Convention “riots”; I may have accidentally voted for Nixon eight times. Now, another Democratic Convention is set in Chicago. It also follows a president’s resignation. But this resignation did not utterly fracture the Democratic Party. Johnson’s record of achievements was amazing, highlighted by the Civil Rights Act. Over six hundred laws were passed in less than four years. But Johnson could not rally the nation behind him, not at all; and neither could Biden. And yet, while these two Chicago conventions sound like twins, in fact, they are utterly different. Yes, Nixon who replaced Johnson turned out to be a criminal, and flamed out. Trump is already legally a criminal, and has been vetted as mentally ill. He makes Nixon seem almost humanistic. The difference lies in their relation to the constitution. However perverse Nixon’s sins were, his own party upheld the constitution, and so did he, when he resigned. The nation-state had antibodies to stop infections like him. Little did we know that firewalls destroyed by Nixon would somehow lead to Trump.

    Let us reverse-angle the shot for a moment and try a world-systems POV. Does 2024 point toward an empire hollowing out? 1968 was a year of inflation and Eurodollar hysteria, as well as a war in Southeast Asia. The difference may be clearer to see from a worldwide perspective. But the soft tissue of the law, those customs that are considered part of the social contract, were still legitimate. Now, the habits of America’s social contract lie in shreds. The Supreme Court, presumably the guardian of legal truth, is now dead set on dismantling the federal balance of powers altogether. On behalf an authoritarian president? How strange indeed, even rather comical somehow. The US is hardly on the edge of economic or even social oblivion. But its collective mind is struggling through a nervous breakdown. That is why I keep a special eye on this matter of solidarity with Harris’s nomination. If this represents a burst of oxygen, it runs against the downward spiral of the past fifty years, despite the glamour after the Cold War, and cell phones that become our AI lovers and protectors.

    The key that drives all this is utterly economic. A squeeze on middle class income has averaged about one percent lost each year since 1979. These statistics are uneven; many factors ratchet the figures up and down. But the perception is real. Most Americans feel more exploited almost year by year. Legislative gridlock adds a forlorn distrust of all government, and with it a growing belief in the fictional deep state. Comparisons to Gilded Age America are frequent, and to a growing feudalism. I would also compare America to Old Regime France in 1760, when the church and nobility were forbidden to pay taxes. The Crown was morally and economically bankrupt. A push to bring back more feudal dues quietly infuriated the masses, and even the commercial elite. Then in 1787, the king ordered an Estates General, to force the obdurate nobles to pay taxes, and get bank debt keepers off his back. Instead, 1787 fired up an insurgency and a solidarity—the rights-of-man-principle–that no one in Europe had seen on this scale, not even from the US, Holland, or Britain. Perhaps 2024 is a kind of 1787. That is another reason why I am watching this solidarity that suddenly appears, after being out of sight for generations. Has the Trump cult pushed beyond its limits? How symbolic was Biden’s old age and frailty, so that his leaving seems for the moment to reverse American morbidity about the future? There have been insurgencies of late on the left. I think of the Occupy Movement in 2011, that drifted away once the tents were removed. The checks and balances system has practically collapsed. 2024 will be an object lesson in how far this collapse has gone.

    I see an ideological turning, no matter who wins. I am guessing that Harris may actually continue to surprise, because so much energy is gathering around her. Trump is much weaker than he looks. Insane bluster is not courage, and a fury of lies is a movement bound to crash. Authoritarianism is perversely symbolic in American mythologies. Just look at action movies and westerns. So I also wonder if the insurgent hysteria is burning itself out, rather than hoping that Americans have come to their senses at last. Perhaps they have. I won’t sponsor more nihilism for the moment.

    One fact is clear: a new constitutional machine for doing politics is beyond necessary. Most definitely 2024 will be a laboratory case. The full measure of where Americans land in 2024 will take twenty to fifty years. I don’t foresee a socialist alternative, but something may yet be afoot. I have decided to vote for the young people I see in my classes, and in my projects. They look so overwhelmed sometimes, but determined. I wish I had a way to deliver the last six hundred years in a backpack, to giver them as much energy and cultural range that America’s mad journey requires. I hope 2024 is a laboratory for some of the young voters. One thing is certain: the catastrophes ahead remind us of worldwide transformations in the past, even why 1968 did not take Americans where they needed to go. The Renaissance, for example, was a rotten time to live for ninety-five percent of Europeans. That is why a religious war began in 1516 that continued essentially for 140 years. 2024 will most certainly be the clearest example of a political and cultural civil war that America has ever faced. Young voters especially believe that our polyvalent crisis is grotesquely unfair. Its economic precarities verge on insane. But the moment itself, as a Renaissance that is a rotten time to live, will be the making of them.

    Norman Klein is an urban historian and media-historian who has been teaching at the California Institute of the Arts for more than forty years. One of his best books is about Los Angeles—The History of Forgetting: Los Angeles and the Erasure of Memory (1997)—and he has, among other books, also written a history of special effects (The Vatican to Vegas: The History of Special Effects, 2004). He is currently at work on a book about the dismantling of the American psyche.

  • Jensen Suther–Marxism as Idealism? Response to Roberts’s “Ideology and Self-Emancipation”

    Jensen Suther–Marxism as Idealism? Response to Roberts’s “Ideology and Self-Emancipation”

    Marxism as Idealism? Response to Roberts’s “Ideology and Self-Emancipation”

    Jensen Suther

    This essay is published in response to William Clare Roberts’s essay “Ideology and Self-Emancipation”.

    The stock of Marxist theorist Georg Lukács has fluctuated wildly since the appearance of History and Class Consciousness in 1923, but in recent years it has once again been on the decline. In a piece from 2019, Endnotes contributor Jasper Bernes rejects Lukács’s key category of consciousness as “confused” and as promoting an unpalatable vanguardism (2019: 200). In his blockbuster book Mute Compulsion, Søren Mau, toeing the classic Althusserian line, identifies Lukács’s Marxism as a “kind of romanticism” and as a humanism (2023: 82). And finally, there is the recent work of William Clare Roberts, which undertakes an ambitious, sustained critique of Lukács as the originator of the Marxist theory of “false consciousness” and as the progenitor of the tradition of ideology critique (2022, 2024). In “Ideology and Self-Emancipation,” published recently on this site, Roberts aims to displace the model of Marxist theory derived from the “Lenin-Lukács-Frankfurt” lineage with a competing theory bearing the names “Lenin-Gramsci-Althusser” and spelled out at the end of the essay with the help, strangely enough, of Wilfrid Sellars. Roberts’ scholarly or textual goal is to recall us to Marx and Engels’ original rejection of the Enlightenment project of dispelling illusions and false consciousness through “rational argumentation.” His deeper conceptual and political goal is to supplant a Marxist project wedded to the notion that “incorrect ideas are a barrier to self-emancipation” with one that understands ideology as the ensemble of material practices and institutions that produce and structure human agency.

    My aim here is not to pick apart Roberts’s readings of classic Marxist texts. While I do find Roberts’s interpretations of The German Ideology and of his evidently abridged edition of History and Class Consciousness forced and often tendentious,[1] what I want to offer here is not a clinic in close reading or a systematic defense of Lukács but a brief, competing account of the idea of a distinctly Hegelian Marxism. I believe that Roberts’s mischaracterization of key concepts in Lukács—especially false consciousness and imputed consciousness—leads him to formulate an incoherent and politically disastrous alternative. But I also think we must go beyond Lukács—beyond Lukács and back to Hegel—if we are to entitle ourselves to a concept that both Lukács and Roberts simply take for granted: a concept of historical agency. The key, Hegelian question raised by History and Class Consciousness, which to my mind has been covered over and greatly distorted over the course of its reception, concerns the conditions of possibility of being not just subject to history (to the “cunning of reason,” as Hegel calls it) but the subjects of history—not in the sense of an infallible sovereignty but in the sense of a recognized responsibility for our actions and form of life and of an openness and vulnerability to possible reasons to act and think otherwise. Lukács arguably presupposes such an account of agency (and Roberts, by virtue of his investment in emancipatory politics, arguably requires it) but—for complex reasons I will only touch on here—the methodological strictures of HCC prohibit Lukács from openly elaborating the assumed metaphysics of freedom.

    I will begin by reconstructing Roberts’s basic picture of ideology critique and his chief criticism of Hegelian Marxism: its understanding of servitude as voluntary and of “false consciousness” as the ground of voluntary servitude. According to Roberts’s opposing account, the oppressed do not consent to their own domination but rather find their servitude necessitated by the way material production is organized. Following this reconstruction, I identify two major problems with Roberts’s approach, a form of institutional determinism that undermines his appeal to Sellars’ “space of reasons” and a form of normative indeterminism that renders his notion of freedom vacuous. I argue that the Hegelian account of rational agency is a necessary corrective. Finally, I return to Lukács’s notion of false consciousness in light of this Hegelian account of agency and defend it against Roberts’s objections.

    To draw on Roberts’s own metaphor, according to the properly Hegelian notion of agency underpinning Lukács’s picture, ideas do not reside in an “incorporeal” “higher plane of pure normativity” but rather constitute the unifying form of living bodies like ours, grounding the very possibility of action and indeed of history. Marxism, on this view, is an idealism, but idealism, properly understood, is precisely not the idea that the world is sovereignly created by a transcendent mind. Rather, idealism is the idea that the source of the authority of both epistemic and pragmatic norms lies in us and that we alone can determine what ought to be believed and “what is to be done.” And as Hegel tells us, such idealism is an objective idealism because such self-determination is an embodied and material process through which we strive to flourish as the sort of animals we are. The point here is not that Roberts is right that ideas are in the head but wrong that they have no influence; the point is that ideas are precisely not in the head but in the world and just thereby the ground of possible servitude or emancipation. It is not the prettiest phrase, but I call this view hylomorphic materialism, for reasons that will become clear.

    I.

    The core of Roberts’s argument concerns a paradox at the heart of much of modern political thought: “If the oppressed can emancipate themselves and are even under an obligation to do so, it is hard to account for why they are not already free without recourse to the paradoxical claim that the oppressed freely choose to be oppressed.” The theory of ideology first developed by Destutt de Tracey in the late eighteenth century attempts to solve this paradox. According to Roberts’s account of de Tracey, ideology is the “science of ideas” through which we can learn to distinguish “true” needs from “false” ones. Our perceptions of the world around us are naturally truthful but are liable to distortion by desire, which mediates our relations to others and constitutes the basis of Destutt’s “liberal political economy.” The task of ideology, on this view, is to teach individuals that their autonomous pursuit of their ends is not ultimately opposed but conducive to the self-determination of others and thus to that of themselves. I satisfy my needs by working to satisfy yours and vice versa. Yet because no social institution or process is immediately accessible in its totality to natural perception, we can be led to desire what might harm us and fail to see our dependence on—and thus need of—institutions we are predisposed to resist. The pedagogical aim of ideology is thus to reconcile us to commercial society, in which the “greatest general prosperity” is achieved precisely through a mutual and generalized form of voluntary servitude.

    Now, according to Roberts, Marx and Engels inherit this notion of ideology from de Tracey—not in the sense that they sign on to his pedagogical project but in the sense that it is that selfsame project they are targeting whenever they see fit to criticize “ideology.” On the standard reading, The German Ideology conceives ideology as a set of (false) ideas promulgated by the ruling class that broadly determines how people act, facilitating their conformity to the prevailing social order. Such ideas manufacture the consent of the oppressed to their own oppression. Drawing on the work of Paul Bowman, Roberts calls this “protagonism-ideology,” according to which changing the world is equivalent to remaking it “either by force of words or so as to make it live up to an ideal.” If we can change what people think, in other words, we can thereby change social reality itself. For Roberts, however, this is not the position Marx and Engels advocate but precisely the Left Hegelian one they reject, in favor of a “sociological materialism” which holds that “practices of production, exploitation, and domination are […] causally prior to and effective apart from religious, intellectual, and political practices of discursive production, howsoever these latter are institutionalized.” Accordingly, servitude is not voluntary but necessary and it is not “in the head,” where the ideas are, but “in the reproduction of life,” beyond the sphere of mere ideas. Far from being an effective tool of oppression, ideology is thus said to be “functionally useless” to the elite and therefore not to constitute a barrier to the self-emancipation of anyone, let alone workers.

    Let us consider the next step in Roberts’s argument, his account of the origin of false consciousness, which is traced to Lenin’s theory of ideology in What Is to Be Done? and is said to have been given its most sophisticated formulation in relation to class struggle in Lukács’s History and Class Consciousness. On one reading of the Leninist program (the one Roberts will resist), the proletariat serves as the practical conduit for the theories and ideas of an intellectual vanguard. The theoretical question that Lukács seeks to answer is how the spontaneous struggles of the masses—for, say, a better wage—can be given a genuinely revolutionary form. According to Roberts’s Lukács, “The only obstacle standing between the proletariat and complete emancipation [is] the absence of a correct ideology.” What Lukács calls class consciousness is meant to furnish the rationally required ideological corrective.

    False consciousness, then, is the difference between what you take your interests to be and what your interests actually are given your membership in the proletarian class. Your “objective” interests lie in whatever would be required to achieve the self-emancipation of the class and, a fortiori, of yourself.  If false consciousness “is equivalent to ideological subjection, or to serving the interests of your oppressors,” then class consciousness is your recognition of “the emancipatory interests of your class.” Roberts takes this to be the difference between crossing a picket line during a strike because it is in one’s immediate interest to do so and recognizing that one’s “true interest” lies in the collective resistance through which, say, better conditions and wages can be won.

    This is a crucial juncture in Roberts’s account, since it is where he first identifies the two main “dangers” of the Lukácsian approach. The first danger is that of “forgetting that our interest in freedom is itself instrumental.” The idea of self-emancipation can suggest that freedom is the end of human life rather than just a means to my individual pursuit of my projects and interests. For Roberts, the “whole reason we ought to want to be free”—and I want to return to that “ought” below—“is because it would allow us to get on with living our lives as we think is best, without having to navigate the extraneous motivations generated by the dominant.” That is, there is no unifying end or value to which we all ought to commit our lives; freedom is merely a precondition for each of us to pursue our contingent and disparate, individual ends. What makes the failure to see this a danger is that it “inflates our interest in freedom into the moral demand to see the world from a purely human standpoint […] ‘of the awakening of humanity to self-consciousness.’” Such a standpoint would not only abstract away from the things that matter to me; it also illicitly assumes freedom as the “essence” of human action, history, and life. This is directly connected to the second danger. As Roberts puts it, the promotion of freedom to the final end of human life relieves the socialist of any hard judgments about our ends, which are always decided in advance; the only burdens are thus “burdens of conscience,” concerning whether or not we are living up to the preestablished “communist morality.” Taken together, both dangers amount to a “betrayal” of the very project of self-emancipation, since they turn “our interest in being free into a self-refuting interest in being without interests.”

    Before I begin to sketch an alternative, we need to get two final elements of Roberts’s account on the table. First, Roberts argues that the most important inheritors of Lukács’s account of false consciousness are the members of the Frankfurt School, who found the tradition of ideology critique proper. According to Roberts’s reconstruction, the critique of ideology in the hands of Theodor Adorno, Max Horkheimer, and others, amplifies the moralistic dimensions of Lukács by focusing not on the social dynamics that impede our “conscious control” and “falsify our normative ideals” but on a critique of all present values and meanings in light of “a posited counterfactual ideal speech situation.” In other words, Roberts reads Jürgen Habermas’s later account of communicative rationality—of transparent, consensus-producing communication grounded in appeal to the force of the better reason—back into the original Frankfurt School method of ideology critique as its unstated yardstick or criterion. Habermas’s discourse-theoretical innovations, on this account, constitute the endpoint of a story that begins with de Tracey’s “science of ideas.”

    And lastly, there is Roberts’s own briefly sketched, alternative picture, which claims Gramsci and Althusser as the true inheritors of the Marxist project of the critique of ideology (in de Tracey’s sense). On this account, ideological hegemony is a function not of false consciousness or incorrect ideas but of the “recruitment and deployment of agents” through a process of “interpellation.” The basic thought is that agents are not responsible for their own servitude through the (false) beliefs that inform their choices; rather, they are constituted as agents of a certain kind by the social structures in which they are imbricated. Ideology is thus no longer restricted to those ideas promulgated by the ruling class but is now to be understood as the score-keeping matrix that makes up the institutional fabric of social life and that regulates behavior through practices of sanction and affirmation. The actions of agents are thus effects of dispositional regularities, which are themselves functions of structure. Now, obviously this smacks of determinism and functionalism, but Roberts believes he has an ace in the hole: if we acknowledge a plurality of competing ideologies, then there is room for countervailing forms of interpellation within a given social order. This is meant to explain “how discursive practices” can effect change in lieu of the “protagonism” rejected by Marx and Engels.

    Roberts’s concluding, and in my view most important, claim is that the social and material fact of domination is in itself “normatively neutral,” making no claim on us; domination only becomes normatively valenced in relation to particular commitments and interests. Correlatively, non-domination (or freedom) is valuable not in itself but only relative to our individual projects and ends, as we already saw above. The importance of this claim lies in what it reveals about Roberts’s understanding of normativity and the agent-relativity of the value of freedom: there is no general, humanity-wide imperative to end domination (“communist morality”); there is only my private interest in ending it, given the specific burdens it imposes on me.

    II.

    The first thing to note about the above account is just how much it takes for granted regarding what it means to be an agent. Roberts is clearly sensitive to and concerned to meet the objection that his Althusserian account is functionalist—that agents’ actions are predetermined by structural laws—but the idea that we can save the notion of agency by multiplying the number of ideologies in play is a nonstarter. Given the basic understanding of the relationship between agent and structure, the pluralization of ideology would just entail more possibilities for being functionalized, not fewer. Social change would still depend not on the actions of agents qua agents (more on this in a moment) but rather on the “chemical” interaction among institutions which interpellate their members. It matters which competing ideologies are at play and whether they ought to be affirmed or disaffirmed. Yet the “sociological materialism” Roberts endorses leaves no room for appeals to reasons as to why one form of interpellation ought to be promoted and another resisted. That multiple ideologies, as a matter of fact, compete for more conscripts does nothing to establish which ideologies are worthy of endorsement; worthy of a theoretical defense; worthy of the ink spilled in the pages of journals. It is useful to recall here Marx’s third thesis on Feuerbach, written in 1845 alongside The German Ideology. “The materialist doctrine that men are products of circumstances and upbringing, that changed men are thus products of different circumstances and a changed upbringing,” Marx chides, “forgets that circumstances must precisely be changed by men and that the educator must himself be educated” (2011: 793).[2] That is, we change our circumstances and are not simply changed by our circumstances, and those responsible for our upbringing are not simply algorithmically responsive to institutional prompting but must themselves be shaped and educated in light of our purposes and ends. The failure to grasp this point, Marx emphasizes, divides society into two parts, the “educator” and the “educated,” granting the former causal priority over the latter. And this results in the very “contemplative materialism” Marx, Engels, and Roberts himself all want to reject, according to which human activity is merely the function of its circumstances, an external object of theoretical contemplation we are powerless to change.

    But to “educate the educator,” for Marx, precisely consists in doing what Roberts claims Marx disavows, namely “criticizing theoretically” as part and parcel of “revolutionizing practically” (2011: 793). Marx’s example here is instructive: for Feuerbach, the task is to show that the religious idea of the holy family has its material basis in the secular family, but for Marx, this does not go nearly far enough. “The fact that the secular basis lifts itself above itself and fixes itself in the clouds as an independent realm,” Marx writes, “is to be explained precisely by the self-division and self-contradiction of this secular basis” (2011:793). Marx’s point here in emphasizing “contradiction” is that the secular family projects an idealized, holy family in order to evade its responsibility for falling short of its own internal principles. This marks a passage from mere contemplation of an object (the family) subject to material laws to a form of critical-historical self-awareness: we become conscious of our reasons for changing our condition, for “revolutionizing in practice” the family form. The critique of the German ideology is thus not meant to show that there is no place in politics for the critique of ideas but rather that the critique of ideas opens onto—and opens up—the space of the political. Without such “consciousness of reasons,” of our sense of what we ought to do (and can thus fail to do), we cannot intelligibly be agents of political change. And as we will see, this undermines the hard distinction Roberts makes toward the end of his essay between the mere “fact” of domination and its normative significance in certain contexts, since there can be no social practice that is not already the consciousness of its own goodness (or badness) and thus of the reasons for sustaining it (or leaving it behind). But what exactly is the alternative conception of agency Marx’s account here presupposes?

    I want to suggest that Marx—and later, Lukács—is tacitly relying on Hegel’s logical-metaphysical account of willing. This may come as a surprise, given Marx’s avowed aim of transforming dialectics into a respectably non-metaphysical, historical science. While this is not the occasion to demonstrate in any detail what Marx misses in his early engagements with Hegel, stated in brief, Hegel is attempting to entitle himself to concepts Marx simply assumes and to show us why social life must be understood—in Marx’s own words—as “essentially practical” and why the domain of objects (“sensuousness”) must be understood as a kind of result of “practical, human-sensuous activity” (2011: 792). This is a “logical-metaphysical” or “non-empirical” account, in other words, because it is derived not through observation or experience but through consideration of what it is to even purport to represent an object or an action.[3] To purport to do something is to claim to know how to do it, which immediately raises the question of the conceptual norms that constitute the measure of such know-how. We cannot learn about the nature of agency by observing how people do act, in order to arrive at a set of psychological laws (e.g., “Actors tend to formulate intentions”); rather, at issue are the concepts that must be operative if an activity is to be so much as intelligible as acting (e.g., “Actors, to be actors, must act in light of an intention”). And since such conceptual constraints cannot be given in experience (there can be no experience without them already up and running), they must be autonomously set by thinking itself, as Hegel’s Science of Logic shows.[4]

    What distinguishes Hegel’s account of the “pure concepts” that thought “gives to itself” from the familiar Kantian one is that they are shown to be determinations not of our subjective representations but indeed of the very meaning of being itself (of what must be true of being, if it is to intelligibly be the concept of “what is”). Hegel, like Kant, holds that concepts function as “predicates of possible judgments,” or in Hegel’s own idiom, that the judgment is the “self-diremption of the concept.”[5] What this means is that concepts derive their sense from the way they are used in judgments; concepts can only be concepts in a “split” subject-predicate relation, wherein they act as rules for how they are to be applied. For example, in designating some object “car,” I thereby specifically rule out reference to it as “train” and am now entitled to other judgments (for example, that it is a vehicle). A “science of logic” concerns those meta-concepts that act as rules for thinking not this or that object but objectivity as such, “being.”[6]  Hegel’s materialism thus consists in his commitment to giving an account of what would constitute a consistent account of what it is to “be” in general; and to thereby grasping the basic “logic” of material reality itself. An insistence like Marx’s that material reality falls outside the conceptual sphere is itself an inconsistent determination of its nature; that is, that concept, the concept of reality, also rules certain things in and certain things out.[7] If the nature of such concepts could be empirically or historically ascertained, then it would be only contingently—rather than essentially—true that social life is practical and historical; there could feasibly be non-historical practices.  Yet this would not only dissolve the concepts (and the phenomena) in question; it would also undermine the very foundations of the materialist project.

    We might take as our starting point Hegel’s key logical claim that all action is self-conscious.[8] The basic thought is that in taking a walk or writing an essay, I must be conscious of myself as walking or as writing. This does not mean that I can only know that I am walking by observing myself doing so, as if “I” were just another object in my environment; I do not infer that I am the one doing the walking from the available sensory evidence. Rather, I can only be conscious of myself walking by being the walker. This is to say that self-consciousness is not consciousness of an object but an attentiveness to what it is to be walking—to the rules that distinguish walking well from walking poorly. Such rules are not imposed from without or only applied in moments of overt reflection; they are instead understood by Hegel as constitutive of the activity itself. It is for this reason that, inversely, I can only be a walker by being conscious of myself as one. I take myself to be bound by such rules, which dictate not what I will do but what I ought to do or have reason to do. In failing to put one foot in front of the other or in failing to pay attention to obstacles in front of me, I do not contradict an external scorekeeper; I am contradicting myself.

    Hegel inherits this fundamentally anti-Cartesian thought from Kant, who had rejected Descartes’s observational and introspective model of self-awareness and replaced it with the radical idea of a “transcendental unity of apperception.”[9] Kant’s chief innovation lies in the claim that the unity of experience is a function of our consciousness of that unity, in virtue of which the understanding spontaneously binds itself to the a priori rules (the categories) for such unification of the objects of experience. In Kant’s practical philosophy, he expands this account of the spontaneity of mind in order to show that practical reason likewise “legislates” its own internal norm, the moral law; through our consciousness of this “ought,” we recognize that we are the exception to laws of nature, since we can always act otherwise than the law commands, and so thereby attain awareness of ourselves as free.[10] The details of this account need not concern us; the point here is that Hegel radicalizes the Kantian notion of self-consciousness in two ways relevant to our discussion of Roberts.

    The first concerns Kant’s ethical monadism. For Kant, every agent, just as an agent, is conscious of the moral law as the overriding principle of autonomous action; the law demands that we treat all others as ends, but our consciousness of the law itself is a solitary, “monadic” affair.[11] This is to say that practical self-knowledge on the Kantian picture is purely a matter of my private understanding of what the law requires. This prompts Hegel to accuse Kant of confusing the most radical evil with the highest good, since if I alone determine what ought to be done, it is always open to me to claim that what the law asks of me just happens to be what I most desire—like the fundamentalist who justifies the most heinous, violent acts by purporting to possess special knowledge of the mind of God.[12] Whether this is a fair criticism of Kant is beside the point; what matters here is the alternative Hegel proposes.

    As we saw above, Hegel shows that my doing something is not such a doing independently of my knowing that I am doing it. In teaching a class, I am conscious of what it is to do so and thus am purporting to adhere to a norm. But since this knowledge is non-observational, I also cannot know that I am doing it without being the embodied doer, and this implies that my action itself manifests—in a way that it does not for Kant—my self-understanding.[13] For Kant, what matters is that I take myself to be acting from duty, regardless of how things might appear; for Hegel, appearances are essential, such that it matters whether I am recognized by others as doing what I take myself to be. To be conscious of norms in acting is thus to be conscious of the (potential) justifiability of one’s act to others. Yet this also opens up the possibility of a discrepancy between my explicit self-understanding and the sort of intentional awareness implicit in the act itself. I can get myself wrong, as when I tell myself I am helping a friend in need while in actuality procrastinating some other task. And this is likely to inflect how I help—distractedly, say. To be acting for reasons—that is, to be acting at all—is to be conscious of what ought to be done, in a way that renders one’s reasons susceptible to contestation by others. And whether we can authoritatively give reasons or bind ourselves to norms will depend, in the end, on whether we confer authority on one another as reasoners, as self-legislators, as inhabitants of the social space of reason.[14]

    Now, an important feature of Roberts’s argument is his own appeal to Wilfrid Sellars’ “space of reasons” idea to reconceive the notion of ideology as well as the relationship between ideas, concepts, and reasons and our practical reality. Strikingly, this argument assumes the form of the classic antinomy between idealism and materialism. On the one hand, ideas are held to exist in the head, and it is sufficient to change the way people think to change the world itself. This is the idealist view associated with the Left Hegelians that Roberts rightly opposes. On the other hand, ideology is the way that individuals are constituted by a discursive context and determined in their acts by institutional rules or reasons. On this materialist view, inspired by Gramsci and Althusser, ideology is decidedly not “in the head” but is instead identical with agents’ embodied, practical reality. Yet this latter conception cannot account for the distinction between a law and a norm or an event and an action and so risks assimilating the space of reasons to the space of causes. If my arm twitches and knocks over a vase, my body is causally responsible for what has happened, the event of the vase falling over. But if, in anger, I intentionally knock over the vase utilizing the same set of motions, then I have acted: I am morally on the hook for what has happened. The motions of the event and the action might be outwardly the same, but they bear radically different forms: the physical movements comprising my act are unified by my consciousness of their end, my reason for so moving. And unlike in the case of the twitch, I can act otherwise and can fail to do what I have reason to do (perhaps it was a Nazi relic and my anger appropriate in this instance). It is this point, not Roberts’s competing ideological apparatuses, that is needed to avoid functionalism.

    To be participating in a practice, then, I must bind myself to institutional norms and thereby assume responsibility for determining what counts as a reason for what (what is permissible and what impermissible in the space of reasons). Discourse itself is unintelligible apart from our holding ourselves to discursive proprieties, “oughts” we can fail to live up to; this is so because it is only in light of such rational normative activity that the content of discourse exhibits determinacy: for example, in judging that it is impermissible to say of something wholly blue that it is wholly red, I determinately articulate the content of the concept of color.[15] Were the concept of color not such a self-consciously applied rule, there would be no necessity to denying the contrary; there could not so much as be blue things as distinct from red ones because there would be nothing that ought to be taken as blue, as specifically not-red. While Roberts rightly recognizes ideology as the “space of reasons,” the concept of the space of reasons is inseparable from the notion of normative self-governance that Roberts rejects. It is because I must always act on the basis of reasons that I am responsible for my actions and beliefs and can be called to account, asked to provide not exculpations (“the ideological apparatus made me do it”) but justifications (“I proposed because I love her” or “I cast a ballot because I am a citizen”).[16] And it is because we must act on the basis of reasons that we are responsible for determining what to do and for potentially changing how we act. The space of reasons is precisely not just a “structure” of interdependently defined roles but the normative process of mutual struggle to determine how we ought to live.

    The above point can be summarized as follows: there can be no ideology without rationality and normativity; and there can be no reasons or norms without autonomy or freedom. Roberts, in rejecting the idea that norms are self-determined, is guilty of what Robert Brandom has characterized as a form of gerrymandering: Roberts demarcates a space of reasons, practices, and institutions, but this amounts to an illicit partitioning (a “gerrymandering”) because, as we have seen, the space of reasons is unintelligible except as the realm of freedom.[17] To genuinely lay claim to that space would be commit to the conception of rational agency that makes it possible.

    There is a second, deeper form of gerrymandering, however, that is systematically missed by theorists of rational agency like Brandom and that is essential to diagnosing the tendency towards antinomian thinking not only in Roberts but in both the idealist and the materialist discourses more broadly. The neo-pragmatist, post-metaphysical reading of Hegel associated with Brandom and others has been heavily influenced by Sellars’ distinction between the “manifest” and “scientific” images.[18] (Not coincidentally, this distinction is also present in Roberts, in the guise of the contrast between normative and empirical facts.) Very roughly, the manifest image is how the world appears from our practical standpoint: certain bodily movements show up for us as intentional acts, just as certain arrangements of matter show up as purposively organized, like tools and organisms. The manifest image is, more or less, just a subjective illusion. The scientific image, by contrast, is not an image of how things manifestly or apparently are, given our practical concerns, but an image of how they really are: what shows up for us as an action is, from the scientific vantage, just an effect of physiological laws and causal principles. What makes the manifest image a form of gerrymandering is that it illicitly carves up material reality in accordance with our practical norms; Hume famously makes this point in noting that no “ought” can be derived from what “is.” But if this is so, then is intentionality itself not an illicit form of demarcation, an instance of gerrymandering? The Hegelian might have a point against Roberts, but the victory is Pyrrhic: he has built his castle in the sky. If Roberts is not entitled to the ideas of action and practice because he lacks commitment to the idea of normative self-determination, is the Hegelian not also hamstrung by his commitment to the manifest/scientific distinction?

    III.

    This brings us to the second of Hegel’s two ways of radicalizing the Kantian account of self-consciousness. In the Science of Logic, Hegel praises Kant for reviving Aristotle’s understanding of living organisms as internally purposive.[19] According to Aristotle, a substance is a composite of matter (hyle) and form (morphe), where the form of a thing lies in its characteristic activity or function. Form, on this account, is the actuality of a substance, individuating its matter as an instance of a kind, and matter is its potentiality for fulfilling its function. It is not that form is added to a preexisting material; form is rather the principle of the unity of matter, dictating what and how things hang together. An organism, then, is a substance par excellence, in that its function is not relative to an external designer, as in the case of a tool, but is internal to the organism itself: its function consists in the activity of unifying and maintaining itself.[20]  Following the rise of Newtonian mechanics, this Aristotelian account of self-movement on the basis of internal principles fell out of favor. Newton introduces a rectilinear understanding of motion, according to which generic masses move measurable distances in space and time under the influence of external forces. This breakthrough was reflected in Descartes’ influential—and still pervasive—understanding of animals as automata that obey the basic laws of matter in motion.[21] Yet in the Critique of the Power of Judgment, Kant raises a serious objection to the modern scientific worldview, arguing that the distinction between animate and inanimate is not so much as intelligible without appeal to the (Aristotelian) concept of inner purposiveness. Disease, injury, and death are not just different states but deficient states, reflecting that something has gone wrong. But in a purely mechanical universe, there is no room for “going wrong.” Hence Kant’s famous line that it would be absurd “to hope that there may yet arise a Newton who could make comprehensible even the generation of a blade of grass according to natural laws.”[22]

    Now, the problem with Kant’s account is that he understands inner purposiveness not as an objective determination of certain kinds of natural objects but as a subjective principle constraining our representations of living beings. In other words, Kant is agnostic about whether anything actually is internally purposive. What Hegel shows, in a complex argument that need not concern us here, is that the intelligible structure of nature collapses if it is taken to be coterminous with the space of causes; nature must also comprise a proto-normative space, the “space of purposes,” if you will, which arises with the most primitive instance of life. It is in light of its purpose of self-maintenance that a cat discriminates instrument from obstacle, good-for from bad-for, in the environment surrounding it. And indeed, it is its evolved species-form that furnishes normative criteria, in relation to its contingent, natural-historical circumstances, for flourishing versus withering. A tiger that loses an eye is a “bad tiger,” not from our zoological standpoint but from its own standpoint, given its purpose of maintaining itself not just willy-nilly but as a tiger. It needs its eyes to hunt—to engage in the vital activity characteristic of its kind.

    Hegel refers to life in a stunning turn of phrase as an “objective idealism,” since the “idea” of an organism—its animating purpose or norm—“is not at all only our reflection on life; it is objectively present in the living subject himself.”[23] It has become popular to refer to laws, norms, or even tendencies, as “emergent” properties of a process, but this is nonsensical.[24] The Aristotelian point Hegel is here making is that living entities cannot so much as be the material things they are except in light of such an animating purpose, which is not emergent but originally constitutive. Without such a form, there would be no material process from which it could emerge.[25] An implication of Hegel’s anti-emergentist view is that some proto-form of autonomy or spontaneity is a condition of possibility of organic life: a tiger is not caused to act by sense impressions of its prey; rather, it is the inner purpose of the tiger that enables the prey to show up as prey, as an object worth going after. This is significant in relation to Roberts because it demonstrates that ideas are not epiphenomenal or “in the head” but in the world. And they are in the world already in the case of non-rational animals not as codifications of behavioral regularities but as principles of self-movement—of a primitive form of self-determination.

    We can now return to Hegel’s account of self-consciousness and its implications for Roberts—in particular, for his own understanding of the relationship between freedom and material interest or desire. Against Kant, Hegel argues that self-consciousness (or “apperception”) is not just a formal condition of the unity of my representations; it is rather the condition of the unity of a certain kind of substance, the rational sort of organism. For Kant, the degree to which we allow our animal desires to determine what we do is the degree to which we have forsaken our freedom and given ourselves over to the “realm of necessity,” to causal laws. Yet the above account establishes that, already in the case of lower-order organisms, desires are not simply causal impingements but are in fact only intelligible as a spontaneous responsiveness to what is good-for or bad-for in the environment. (Otherwise, the rusting of a piece of metal and an antelope crying out in pain would be formally indistinguishable, and we would lose the distinction between a difference that matters (a defect) and one that does not (a mere change of state).) Spontaneity or autonomy thus has its basis in nature, not outside of it. This does not mean, however, that self-consciousness is just a capacity for overt reflection on desires that we share with the other animals. Rather, self-consciousness is constitutive of our desires, meaning that we cannot desire at all without being conscious of the desirability of what we desire; self-consciousness is the form without which our matter (our bodies) would fall apart.[26] To feel pangs of hunger, for example, is to feel the force of one’s reasons to eat and to thereby be sensitive to potential justifications for eating that others would accept. This suggests that, in the case of animals like us, we do not just desire this or that but desire to be recognized as desiring rightly, or as one ought to desire. We can maintain ourselves as animals, in other words, only through initiation into the social space of reasons.

    The profound implication of this line of argument for Hegel is that my attempt to satisfy my desires affects what other agents would otherwise be able to do; I must thus be able to justify to others the desires I choose to satisfy as well as how I satisfy them.[27] Whether my reasons actually have the authority I take them to will depend on whether that authority is recognized by others—and whether they themselves are authorized to confer such recognition. And if they are not, the question will arise as to whether their reasons for acting are truly theirs, and not just alien ends or norms imposed from without. Hegel will claim that we can only “actually” be the free agents we have always potentially been through commitment to what he calls the “rational system of the will”—a system of interests, ends, and institutions that enable and exemplify our mutual exercise of our freedom.[28]  Hegel tries to show that no rational, historically situated, self-conscious sort of animal could fail to be motivated to sustain such a system.

    The point for Roberts, by contrast, is that “freedom from domination” is not a self-determined norm but “a basic good” and that domination itself is “normatively neutral.” Freedom is not itself an end but a mere means to the fulfillment of my actual end, my satisfaction of my contingent interests. And domination is only positively normatively valenced to the extent that it precludes me from the pursuit of my interests. Yet one should take note of just how abstract and indeterminate an individual’s “interests” are on this account. Given that freedom for Roberts is just one interest among others and that our participation in institutions that secure our freedom is merely strategic or instrumental, our interests themselves appear to exist prior to and apart from our membership in society. Such an account presupposes the satisfaction of one’s own individual interests as an overriding, transhistorical interest. And this presupposes in turn a quite historically specific, and here undertheorized, conception of individual agency as end-setting prior to and in independence of the socially formative process through which we come to have interests and ends in the first place. Marx makes exactly this point in his critique of Feuerbach, who is said to miss that “the abstract individual whom he analyses actually belongs to a particular form of society” (2011: 794).  It is only under such egoist—indeed, bourgeois or capitalist—assumptions that one could imagine a pre-institutional individual taking a state of non-domination or “freedom” to be a means to the realization of her self-interest.

    Marx’s criticisms here of egoism in Feuerbach are, strikingly, anticipated by Hegel’s own critique of Rousseau in passages like the following:

    If the state is confused with civil society and its determination is equated with the security and protection of property and personal freedom, the interest of individuals as such becomes the ultimate end for which they are united; it also follows from this that membership of the state is an optional matter. – But the relationship of the state to the individual is of quite a different kind. Since the state is objective spirit, it is only through being a member of the state that the individual himself has objectivity, truth, and ethical life. Union as such is itself the true content and end, and the destiny of individuals is to lead a universal life: their further particular satisfaction, activity, and mode of conduct have this substantial and universally valid basis as their point of departure and result. (1991: 276/§258)

    Stated in this way, without any argument, the assertion that the individual “has objectivity and truth […] only through being a member of the state” is hardly dispositive. But there is a powerful argument for this point that Hegel makes in other places and is here taking for granted. If it is established that domination is bad for me, because it inhibits my pursuit of my interests, then it is not “normatively neutral” but in fact bad for all, since I cannot be free from domination unless all others are. If domination were normatively neutral, there would be no reason to prefer domination to non-domination; indeed, it would be a matter of mere preference. But by Roberts’s own lights, I have reason to oppose domination in my case (the burdens it imposes on me), and that reason—as a reason—will have force for any other agent similarly situated, dictating what she ought to do. Given that my own freedom from domination will affect and constrain other agents, limiting what they can do, I must thus take them into account. I have the authority or normative standing to demand that others respect my freedom if and only if I recognize their authority and standing to recognize mine.

    Yet if, as in Roberts’s picture, I have only strategic reasons for coordinating with others, as soon as it is to my advantage to renege on my promise, then I have a good reason to do so. Because the “ultimate end” is the “interest of individuals,” association with others will always appear as a negative restriction. This sort of egoism is not just the formal condition of setting and having ends but is itself a substantive end, a principle of self-satisfaction that we must be able to justify to one another. “Once this principle is accepted,” Hegel writes, “the rational [the demand for justification] can of course appear only as a limitation on the freedom in question” (1991: 58/§29) The problem, then, is that such a principle itself contradicts the forms of cooperation, mutuality, and trust that would be required to sustain it. And this is exactly the point Marx makes about capitalism, initially in On the Jewish Question: “The sphere in which man acts as a communal being is degraded to a level below the sphere in which he acts as a partial being. […] It is not man as citoyen, but man as bourgeois who is considered to be the essential and true man.” (1973: 164). It is eerie just how closely Roberts’s positive picture of an emancipated society parallels the form of life Marx is here calling into question. For Roberts, my “communal being” (my cooperation with others to secure our freedom or non-domination) is subordinated to my “partial being,” the interests I am above all committed to satisfying. It is worth quoting Marx’s strikingly Hegelian response to this model at some length:

    Only when the real, individual man re-absorbs in himself the abstract citizen, and as an individual human being has become a genus-being [Gattungswesen] in his everyday life, in his particular work, and in his particular situation, only when man has recognized and organized his ‘forces propres’ as social forces, and consequently no longer separates social power from himself in the shape of political power, only then will human emancipation have been accomplished. (1973: 168)

    A detailed consideration of genus-being here would take us too far afield, but it is worth noting that the idea of a species conscious of its own normative requirements (its inner purpose) is nothing other than the Hegelian notion of rational life considered above.[29] What Marx is hinting at here is precisely a rationally articulated system of interests, desires, and ends—or the Hegelian idea invoked earlier of a “rational system of the will”—in which the community is not simply a restriction on individual end-setting or just an “enabling condition” of the private pursuit of interests. Such conceptions—like Roberts’s—remain confined within the capitalist imaginary.

    Rather, Hegel’s point is that freedom is not just a condition for pursuing one’s desires or interests but a specific set of ends themselves that we must come to espouse if we are to be the agents we take ourselves to be and live genuinely self-determined lives. As noted above, desire in our case is only intelligible as self-conscious—as the consciousness of the desirability of what we desire (of its justifiability to other agents). And it is owing to this self-consciousness of desire that we can be responsive to the rational requirement to revise our desires. This indicates a “drive” within desire itself to a rational and sharable set of desires and ends, which are precisely not, therefore, merely assumed and imposed from without. On Roberts’s conception, by contrast, what is to prevent my ends from including dealing heroin, polygamy, or anti-Black propagandizing? The problem is that Roberts’s notion of freedom is indifferent to content; and as soon as one starts putting restrictions on content (ruling out obviously abhorrent, historically obsolete practices like slavery, vassalage, indentured servitude, and so on), it will quickly become clear that our interest must lie in mutually justifiable practices, that is, practices in which we mutually regard ourselves as the authors. This will entail, for Hegel, a certain form of the family (of how we reproduce ourselves individually), of work (of how we reproduce one another collectively), and of politics (of how we collectively decide how our form of life is to be structured). For example, if, in taking myself to be a spouse and in inheriting the various responsibilities and entitlements of such a role, I am supposed to act as a unilateral patriarchal authority, those in my household who recognize my authority will themselves lack the normative standing to do so; my authority will thereby be undermined. The failure of patriarchy as a model of normative authority in the sphere of romantic or erotic or reproductive interest begins to tell us something about what a viable interest in that sphere would have to be. Or said differently, freedom itself must be our highest end; the content of our ends that the condition of freedom or non-domination is meant to secure must be freedom itself.

    Now, it must be emphasized that all of the above is supposed to follow, on Hegel’s account, just from our attempts to satisfy our desires in a distinctly self-conscious way. Hegel is not dogmatically asserting freedom “as the end of human life,” in Roberts’s words. We discover through the historical experience of failed attempts at mutuality that freedom must be our end, that there is no livable alternative. This implies that, on the Hegelian account, human beings do will their own condition of slavery and servitude and (potentially) learn from its failure, but this claim must be made with care. Slavery is not simply “voluntary” (or a “choice,” as Ye notoriously put it). To recognize a master’s authority and to abide by his commands is to take there to be a reason for doing so—the value of one’s own life, for example. Bondage carries justificatory weight because it appears to enable me to satisfy my interest in living my life. In the master-slave dialectic, it is the experience of servitude and the fear of death that first teaches the slave the value of her own life. But she also learns from the experience the dispensability of the master. The threat of violence, the slave comes to realize, lacks normative authority precisely because it preempts authoritative recognition by the slave. As Hegel puts it, “It is in the nature of the case [Sache] that the slave has an absolute right to free [herself], and that, if someone has agreed to devote his ethical life to robbery and murder, this is null and void in and for itself, and anyone is entitled to revoke such a contract” (1991: 97/§66A). The master-slave dialectic thereby establishes domination not as a normatively neutral condition but as the original and abiding normative defect to which no one can be indifferent, because it is an obstacle for master and slave alike to a free and flourishing life.

    In other historical episodes, as in (Hegel’s account of) the Roman Empire, the promise of “legal personhood” and a limited individual right to property paves the way to subjection to the whims of a tyrant; domination is accepted in the guise of non-domination. Yet this is not simply “false consciousness”; the Roman way of life constituted a partial, imperfect advance through the introduction of the rational idea—an idea people had good reasons to endorse—of state recognition of personhood. That idea was not just a lie contradicted by an opposed reality but an idea that itself proved contradictory in what its own actualization demanded. The state recognition of personhood, in other words, would have to be radically revised to be properly realized—as it later was, for Hegel, in the modern state.

    IV.

    I want to conclude by addressing Roberts’s understanding of Lukács as moralistic and of class consciousness as impositionist. We have already seen how our interests cannot be abstract and indeterminate in the way Roberts thinks because (1) “interest” in general already bears a proto-rational, purposive shape in the case of other living beings and (2) the interests of self-conscious agents—just to be the determinately contentful interests that they are—must always be the consciousness of their own goodness or justifiability. Such interests become increasingly rationally articulate through the historical struggle to determine which sorts of reasons and norms are actually viable, mutually sharable, including the norms that establish the source of normative authority itself. I call this view hylomorphic materialism because it understands concepts, rules, and norms as the form (morphe) of the matter (hyle) of animals like us. Our modes of production, accordingly, cannot be specified independently of our normative self-understanding regarding how we ought to reproduce ourselves.

    According to Roberts, Lukács’s notion of “imputed” or class consciousness represents a form of moralism (or Moralität, a Hegelian term of art). Roberts takes this to mean that the class-conscious proletariat “sees all, knows all, and acts only and always for the sake of humanity as a whole.” This constitutes a “perverse betrayal of the entire project of self-emancipation,” Roberts writes, “since it turns our interest in being free into a self-refuting interest in being without interests.” The moral ideal of “human freedom” displaces the actual interests of the members of the class.

    I find this questionable as an illustration of Hegel’s critical notion of Moralität, but I will hold that issue to one side. The real difficulty here lies in the tendentious characterization of class consciousness as an alien imposition on the working class and as a form of practical “omniscience.” Consider first the claim that the revolutionary commitment to freedom is at odds with the actual interests of the individual revolutionary. What Roberts ignores in Lukács’s picture is his insistence that the “antagonism between momentary interest and ultimate goal” must be “inwardly overcome” (my emphasis) (1971: 73). This is to say that the immediate interest of the member of the class is not simply cast aside and “sacrificed” for the sake of the interest of the class; rather, the immediate interest cannot be satisfied on its own terms and so rationally necessitates movement towards the “ultimate goal.” To take Marx’s own example, the trade unionist motto of “a fair day’s wages for a fair day’s work” is structurally impossible under capitalist conditions and so gives way to the “revolutionary watchword: ‘Abolition of the wages system!’” (1976: 61).

    More fundamentally, the basic interest of the worker lies in the freedom the wage system purports to provide, namely, the freedom to lead a self-determined life. But it is precisely that freedom that is contradicted by the necessity of laboring for a wage. Class consciousness does not compete with one’s own interests; it is rather the consciousness of what the realization of one’s own interest in freedom would actually require. As Lukács himself puts this point, “Only when the immediate interests are integrated into a total view and related to the final goal of the process do they become revolutionary, pointing concretely and consciously beyond the confines of capitalist society” (1971: 71). Contrary to Roberts’s claim that the aim of the revolution for Lukács is “to make revolutionaries [i.e., those who sacrifice themselves for the external end of freedom] rather than to make revolutionaries unnecessary,” the point is exactly the opposite: “The proletariat only perfects itself by annihilating and transcending itself, by creating the classless society through the successful conclusion of its own class struggle” (1971: 80). And this is so because—as we saw above—one can only successfully constitute oneself as an agent by willing freedom as one’s own end.  

    This bears directly on our final point. Far from relieving the socialist of her responsibility to reflect on her own ends, as Roberts contends, the ideal of freedom as our highest end is itself arrived at through a historical process defined by an increasingly radical form of self-scrutiny. Habermas’ transcendentally derived, “counterfactual ideal speech situation,” which Roberts suggests is the organic endpoint of the Lukácsian tradition of ideology critique, is precisely the wrong model. Rather, for Lukács, it is through the contradictory experience of false consciousness—of, say, the unfreedom of wage labor as freedom—that a possibility of a higher form of knowledge is generated. The “apperceptive” responsiveness such experience exemplifies, the responsiveness to the potential need for self-correction, is what constitutes the opening for Marxist theory—for the sort of work we are trying to do.

    Jensen Suther is currently a Junior Fellow in the Harvard Society of Fellows. He recently completed his first book, Spirit Disfigured: The Persistence of Freedom in Modernist Literature and Philosophy.

    References

    Anscombe, G.E.M. 1981. “The First Person.” In Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Mind by G.E.M. Anscombe, 21-36. The Collective Philosophical Papers of G.E.M. Anscombe Vol. 2. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Aristotle. 2017. De Anima. Translated by C.D.C. Reeve. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    —. 2016. Metaphysics. Translated by C.D.C. Reeve. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Bernes, Jasper. 2019. “Revolutionary Motives.” In Endnotes 5: The Passions and the Interests: 193-246.

    Boyle, Matthew. 2016. “Additive Theories of Rationality: A Critique.” European Journal of Philosophy 24: 527-555.

    Brandom, Robert. 1994. Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    —. 2012. “Reason, Genealogy, and the Hermeneutics of Magnanimity.” Unpublished.

    Conant, James. 2012. “Two Varieties of Skepticism.” In Rethinking Epistemology, edited by Günter Abel and James Conant, 1-76. Vol. 2. Berlin Studies in Knowledge Research, 2 vols. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Hegel, G.W.F. 1991. Elements of the Philosophy of Right. Edited by Allen W. Wood and translated by H.B. Nisbet. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    —. 2010a. Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline. Part I: Science of Logic. Translated by Klaus Brinkmann and Daniel O. Dahlstrom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    —. 1988. Introduction to The Philosophy of History. Translated by Leo Rauch. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    —. 1975. Lectures on Fine Art. Translated by T.M. Knox. Vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    —. 2018. The Phenomenology of Spirit. Translated by Terry Pinkard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    —. 2010b. The Science of Logic. Translated by George Di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Kant, Immanuel. 2000. Critique of the Power of Judgment. Edited by Paul Guyer and translated by Paul Guyer and Eric Mathews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    —. 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and edited by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    —. 1997. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated and edited by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Khurana, Thomas. 2023. “Genus-Being: On Marx’s Dialectical Naturalism.” In Nature and Naturalism in Classical German Philosophy, edited Luca Corti and Johannes-Georg Schülein, 246-278. New York: Routledge.

    Lukács, Georg. 1971. History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics. Translated by Rodney Livingstone. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Malm, Andreas. 2018. The Progress of This Storm: Nature and Society in a Warming World. London: Verso.

    Marx, Karl. 1993. Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy. Translated by Martin     Nicolaus. New York: Penguins Books.

    —.1976. Wage-Labour and Capital & Value, Price and Profit. New York: International Publishers.

    Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. 2011. Gesamtausgabe (MEGA). Friedrich Engels Werke: Artikel Entwürfe Mai 1883 bis September 1886. Edited by Renate Merkel-Melis. Vol. XXX/I. Gesamtausgabe (MEGA). Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

    —. 1973. Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW). Vol. 3: Marx and Engels 1843-1844. London: Lawrence & Wishart.

    Mau, Søren. 2023. Mute Compulsion: A Marxist Theory of the Economic Power of Capital. London: Verso.

    McDowell, John. 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Ng, Karen. 2015. “Ideology Critique from Hegel and Marx to Critical Theory.” Constellations 22, no. 3: 393-404.

    Pinkard, Terry. 1994. Hegel’s Phenomenology: The Sociality of Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Pippin, Robert. 2019. Hegel’s Realm of Shadows: Logic as Metaphysics in The Science of Logic. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    —. 1991. “Idealism and Agent in Kant and Hegel.” The Journal of Philosophy 88, no. 10: 532-541.

    Roberts, William Clare. 2022. “The Red Pill: Breaking Out of The Class Matrix.” Radical Philosophy 2, no. 13: 57-65.

    —. 2024. “Ideology and Self-Emancipation: Voluntary Servitude, False Consciousness, and the Career of Critical Social Theory,” in b2o.

    Rödl, Sebastian. 2021. “Freedom as Right.” European Journal of Philosophy 29: 624-633.

    Rosen, Robert. 1991. Life Itself: A Comprehensive Inquiry into the Nature, Origin, and Fabrication of Life. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Sellars, Wilfrid. “Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man.” In In the Space of Reasons: Selected Essays of Wilfrid Sellars, edited by Kevin Scharp and Robert Brandom, 369-410. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Suther, Jensen. 2023. Forthcoming-A. “The Desire for Desire: Hegel’s Constitutive Model of Rationality in Chapter IV.”

    —. 2023. “Hegel’s Metaphysics of Rational Life: Overcoming the Pippin-Houlgate Dispute.” Hegel Bulletin: 1-32.

    —. Forthcoming-B. Spirit Disfigured: The Persistence of Freedom in Modernist Literature and Philosophy.

    I want to thank Alex Gourevitch, Yanis Molindris, and Alejandro Fernández Barcina, for several conversations that contributed in decisive ways to the development of the argument in this essay. 

    [1] Strikingly, Roberts never cites or discusses the book’s crucial, final chapter, which is where Lukács theorizes the communist party as the context in which the acquisition of theoretical knowledge of capital as a system (a “totality”) becomes possible and assumes the form of a highly precarious and defeasible collective praxis.

    [2] I cite here Engels’ revised version of Marx’s text, which preserves and, in my view, amplifies its spirit.

    [3] On the investigation of the “objective purport” or the world-directedness of thought as the defining Kantian innovation, see Brandom 1994, 6-7. See also Conant (2012).

    [4] See Pippin (2019).

    [5] See Kant 1998, A69/B94. See Hegel 2010b, 552/12.55

    [6] And Hegel pursues such an account independently of consideration of any limiting “forms of sensibility” or “pure forms of intuition,” responsible for ensuring thought’s constraint by a reality outside it. That is because Hegel shows that that very notion of “reality” is itself a pure thought-determination, not a thought-alien “thing in itself,” but this claim must be carefully distinguished from the claim that thought produces the empirical objects it thinks. See Hegel 2010a, 83-85/§41.

    [7] Consider the opening move of Hegel’s Logic. To try to claim—as Parmenides does—that being is simply “what is” and that whatever is not is thereby excluded from being has an unexpected result: on that conception of being, not only are motion and change illusory, since they involve transition to states that are not; one thing cannot be distinguished from another because we do not have license to say that this is not that. That is, no entity can be the determinate entity it is, since such determinacy requires a basic form of negative difference. This is meant to show that such a conception of being, of how things are, fails. If we are to make sense of the concept of being (if we are to make sense of what it means for things to be), we must conceive being differently. The task of a Science of Logic is, at bottom, to determine how to think being consistently. See Hegel 2010b, 59/21.68-69. See also Suther (2023).

    [8] See Hegel 1988, 20-21.

    [9] For an important account of Kant’s critique of Descartes (and the limits of that critique), see McDowell 1994, 101-104.

    [10] See Kant 1997, 53/4:448.

    [11] See Rödl 2021, 631ff.

    [12] See Hegel 2018, 382/662.

    [13] For the classic account of non-observational knowledge, see Anscombe (1981). Anscombe’s account has heavily influenced the “analytic” reception of German Idealism.

    [14] This is Terry Pinkard’s important reformulation of Sellars’ idea. See Pinkard 1994, 7-8.

    [15] See the powerful critique of the “semantically naïve” character of genealogical and structuralist approaches discourse in Brandom (2012).

    [16] For the distinction between exculpations and justifications, see McDowell 1994, 8.

    [17] See Brandom 1994, 36.

    [18] See Sellars (2007).

    [19] See Hegel 2010a, 277/§204.

    [20] See Book II of Aristotle (2017) and Book IX of Aristotle (2016).

    [21] The “machine metaphor” that Descartes introduces remains extremely influential; indeed, the ongoing attempt to engineer AGI presupposes that the mind is a “biological computer” reproducible in a lab. Yet a “computer” cannot itself determine what counts as worth doing or believing; the activity of any machine is parasitic on the values and beliefs of a designer who cannot herself, therefore, be a machine. It is a supreme irony that, instead of overcoming a theological, creationist picture, the machine metaphor reinforces it: if all biological entities are machines, then it follows that someone must have designed and created them. See Chapter 20 in Rosen (1991).

    [22] See Kant 2000, 271/5:400.

    [23] See Hegel 1975, 1:123.

    [24] See, for example, Mau 2023, 43ff. His account is influenced by Malm (2018). The logical point here is that the purposive form of a living whole cannot be an “emergent property” that results from the interaction of its parts because the purposive form is the ground of the parts. The parts of such a whole could not so much as be parts prior to the emergence of their form; they therefore could not “give rise” to anything. It is also worth emphasizing that purpose, unity, principles, forms, and so on are not “properties,” emergent or otherwise; they are that in virtue of which a thing can have properties. Marx, like Hegel, was steeped in the Aristotelian hylomorphic logic, and Marxist interpreters would do well to heed this fact.

    [25] The Aristotelian way of making the anti-emergentist point is to say that actuality is “prior” to potentiality in terms of the account (logos) and of substance (ousia). See Chapter VIII of Book IX of Aristotle (2016).

    [26] See Suther (forthcoming-a) and Boyle (2016).

    [27] For a concise statement of this argument, see Pippin (1991).

    [28] Hegel 1991, 51/§19.

    [29] It is also worth noting that, contrary to the common wisdom, Marx continues to employ the term Gattungswesen in the same sense in the 1850s, in the Grundrisse; see Marx 1973, 243. This suggests a deeper continuity between the early and the late Marx than is usually acknowledged. But beyond this philological issue, there is the substantive philosophical question as to the defensibility of such a concept, which has long been criticized as “humanist.” For a recent example, see Mau 2023, 93. There have been a number of important recent defenses of the concept, such as Khurana (2023) and Ng (2015), but I do not believe that they grasp Marx’s notion in its full radicality. In my forthcoming book, Spirit Disfigured: The Persistence of Freedom in Modernist Literature and Philosophy, I pursue a rethinking of the notion of a Gattungswesen in the context of a systematic grounding of a hylomorphic materialism. This essay exploits one of the key lines of argument developed in the book: the notion that rationality is constitutive of the sorts of living, material beings we are.

  • Dimitris Christopoulos–Greece At the Fiftieth Anniversary of its Republic: 1974-2024

    Dimitris Christopoulos–Greece At the Fiftieth Anniversary of its Republic: 1974-2024

    Greece At the Fiftieth Anniversary of its Republic:1974-2024

    Dimitris Christopoulos

    “Walls” (C.P. Cavafy, 1896, 1987)

    With no consideration, no pity, no shame,
    they have built walls around me, thick and high.

    And now I sit here feeling hopeless.
    I can’t think of anything else: this fate gnaws my mind –

    because I had so much to do outside.
    When they were building the walls, how could I not have noticed!

    But I never heard the builders, not a sound.
    Imperceptibly they have closed me off from the outside world.

    In 2024, Greeks were discovered by pollsters to be “the most stressed people in Europe.” This finding overturns a stereotype, but it makes sense. Market forces, climate forces, and anti-democratic forces once again roil the country, as they did at the beginning of the financial crisis. Yet this time, the disturbance is not the product of a breakthrough, as back in 2010, but of a slow and painful—almost “imperceptible”, to borrow from C.P. Cavafy’s “Walls”–continuation: a silent, further shrinking of the rule of law and the withdrawal of social bulwarks, institutional checks and balances, and political resistance.

    The fragmentation of the Greek opposition is a product of Syriza’s strategic defeat in the course of 2023, and its subsequent and shocking transformation into a party closer to Independent Greeks (Anel), its populist right-wing governmental partner from 2015 to 2018. This is an ominous scenario for the Hellenic Republic: that of a democracy without an opposition.

    This scenario is unfolding in the year in which Greece celebrates the 50th anniversary of the “Metapolitefsi,” the restoration of democracy after the end of the colonels’ regime in 1974.

    This text attempts to summarize some highlights of this trajectory.

    In politics, voters are more likely to notice what we are right now than what we say we wish to become. This was the sad truth behind Syriza’s electoral failure of 2023. What goes around comes around. However, what went around in 2023 and what will come around in 2024 has a history that goes back a long way.

    It all started with the “double electoral earthquake” of 2012, when it seemed that the rising star on the Greek political scene in the place of the crumbling socialist party (Pasok) would surely be Syriza. The star shone, but not for long. Its radiance lasted as long its anti-austerity narrative carried conviction. When the narrative collapsed in that staggering summer of 2015, when the party reluctantly accepted the harsh terms of the EU bailout rather than leave the EU, and lost its parliamentary majority as key members abandoned it, the flaws were all too brightly illuminated. Syriza managed to win the September 2015 election, but by the following day it was clear that the uphill climb was too steep. Without the possibility of escaping the loathsome memoranda of the bail-out agreements, Syriza had lost its political dynamism. The simple answer to today’s plunging polling numbers is that, after a certain point, the people had begun to abhor Syriza, just as from the summer of 2011 to 2015 they abhorred those then in power. This is what the grind of the memoranda entailed: sacrificing a progressive political cohort to save the economy.

    Syriza, with the responsibility of all its bigwigs who allowed it, had been transformed into a personality cult. Thus the main focus of disapproval concerned its leader. And while Tsipras generated enthusiasm with his political talent, he also generated personal revulsion, which after the period of opposition from 2019 to 2023, reached unmanageable and irreversible levels.

    The 31.5% obtained by Syriza in 2019 was unhoped for, but it was also a poisonous gift. It obscured the party’s structural deficits by making the Syriza leadership believe that “rain or shine,” one third of the Greek people would be on its side. The barren years of opposition that followed, 2019–2023, showed that nothing was more untrue. The double electoral earthquake of 2023 only proved the point.

    After the double defeat of that summer and Tsipras’s resignation, it was obvious that, in the absence of the glue between Syriza’s different worlds supplied by the personality of its former leader, the party would not last. And thus came the election of the new leader, Stefanos Kasselakis. Kasselakis is a former high-level employee of Goldman Sachs and as such an unlikely figurehead for a left-wing party. However, the election of the new leader was not just one bad moment. It was a consequence of the many previous bad moments that have been piling up. Yet no one dared to speak out, with few exceptions.

    Since the autumn of 2015, Syriza has been like an iceberg in a heatwave, imperceptibly melting away as ever-increasing temperatures become commonplace.

    Only seen this way, in the medium term, if not long term, can we realize that the supposed “split” of 2023 was in fact the acceleration of an already advanced disintegration. The departure of officials after the election of a new leader is merely one moment in a long historical process of departures and transformations that began with the earlier split that followed the 2015 capitulation to the austerity program of the bankers.

    The most dramatic result of the 2023 departures from Syriza is the formation of a new parliamentary group called the “New Left.” The appearance of the New Left was accompanied by high hopes among many progressives. Yet the New Left performed badly in the European parliamentary elections of June 2024, and this seems most likely due to its resemblance to the old Syriza. The Greek Left is searching for something more.

    Within Syriza, under its new leadership, a rapid process of political bloodletting is now taking place, leading to a political identity that seems new but had in fact begun to gestate within the party since 2019. This new political identity is the transformation of Syriza into a political type of “anything goes” opportunism. Nothing is out of bounds; liberalism and statism are equally acceptable. As are both pro- and anti-immigrant discourse: the party’s leader accused the conservatives of inviting in Pakistani migrants and labelled this an “Islamabad agenda.” The party has gestured both toward the “traditional values of Greek society” and toward a “return to the future.” Toward a glorification of labour and a glorification of capital. And many more paradoxes. One clear certainty is that Syriza as a principled anti-rightist party is heading towards its historical end, the same fate that befell the supposed socialism of Pasok between 2010 and 2012.

    Another certainty is that this process did not occur in 2023, nor can it be charged (or credited, depending on one’s perspective) to its new leader. For this reason, the claim that Syriza split after Kasselakis’s election is incongruous. The leader’s “unmediated” relationship with the party’s people, i.e. a relationship free of the baggage of any procedures that hint at democratic collectivity within a living party, is not Kasselakis’s invention. The road had been paved by the previous incumbent. In this sense, then, despite the obvious discrepancies and differences, the current Syriza leadership is a continuation of the previous one.

    But in any case, if the Italian Communist Party of a Togliatti, of a Berlinguer, ended up via D’Alema in the neoliberal caricature of a Renzi, it is not historically inconsistent for the Syriza of Tsipras to end up in the neoliberal caricature we see in the party of Kasselakis. I mean this without any sarcasm.

    Fifty years after the founding of the Third Hellenic Republic in 1974, after the fall of the U.S.-backed military dictatorship, the Right is setting an agenda on its own, unchecked. For a country that until a few years ago was treated by many in the EU as an austerity-era equivalent of the village of indomitable Gauls in Asterix, fighting off the Roman legions of Julius Caesar with the help of a magic potion, the development is, if not unthinkable, hard to take.

    Note, however, that the problem is not the Right’s political hegemony, but its conditions: a feeble opposition, one-sided control of the media, the fragmentation of social movements, and the manipulation of independent authorities and the judiciary. The problem is not in itself the 41% that the Right got in the national elections. We have seen 41% and even 48% before. Karamanlis in 1974, when the Third Hellenic Republic was beginning its journey, got 54%, but in the aftermath of the junta, he set the agenda only by compromising with a strong social opposition.

    The issue today is the cumulative absence of social bulwarks, political resistance and institutional checks and balances. From the economic crisis to the pandemic and from the pandemic to the energy and climate crisis, democracy itself is suffering. And it suffers more when the opposition is virtually absent, something that is now typical in Greece. In a resolution adopted by the European Parliament on 7 February 2024, its members sounded the alarm on the steep decline of the rule of law in Greece. An infamous wiretapping scandal, the unresolved murder of journalist Giorgos Karaivaz, the Tempi train crash, systematic pushbacks of refugees and migrants in Greek waters, together with the intimidation of journalists, the undermining of independent authorities, the shrinking space for civil society and media pluralism, are all symptoms of democratic backsliding.

    Yet this time, it is the European Parliament, and not anti-government NGOs (the usual suspects for the Greek government), calling “on the Greek government to restore independent authorities, ensure unhindered investigations into the illegitimate wiretappings and implement the recommendations of the Parliament’s PEGA [Pegasus] Committee”. MEP Sophie in ’t Veld emphasised that the EU needs to take its own lessons from the past: “We have seen democracy and the rule of law backslide in a number of EU member states. We know what the signs are, and Greece is showing them right now. Unlike Viktor Orbán, the Greek government puts up a friendly face towards the EU, but this is no reason to keep EU scrutiny at arms-length. We cannot make the same mistake of wait and see, like we did with Hungary and Poland.”

    The most alarming development here is that the strongest reaction to the European Parliament resolution did not come from the Greek government itself but from the plenary of the Greek Supreme Court. Paradoxically enough, the Greek judges (by a majority of 49 to 13) on 15 February deemed it appropriate to answer to a political body, the European Parliament, and slammed the resolution as a “direct interference in the work of the Greek judicial authorities, regarding a series of cases that are pending before the courts, with unproven and unsubstantiated allegations.”

    Such a reaction from a national judiciary body in 2024 is unheard of.

    The unprecedented situation that Greece finds itself in today is in effect a herald of illiberal characteristics in the polity.

    The most glaring proofs that democracy is degenerating in Greece, though not in Greece alone, include:

    1. Direct control of the secret services and public television by the top of the executive branch.
    2. Deactivation of the independent authorities.
    3. Devaluation of parliamentary control.
    4. Lack of media pluralism.
    5. Manipulation of the heads of the judiciary.
    6. Consolidation of an all-powerful government with no visible possibility of change.

    Impressive as it is, this democratic degeneration cannot be properly thought of as an unexpected disaster. A morbidity that until recently would have seemed out of bounds has become familiar. The old boundaries and barriers have dropped from sight. We waited for it, and we did not realize that it was already happening. Evil, then, is not only the emergence of the unknown but the continuation of what we knew too well but proved unable to avoid.

    For this reason, the picture of the future of the Third Hellenic Republic does not inspire optimism. “Natural” disasters–fires and floods–are recurring to the extent that they have now become a permanent emergency. A country that has received so many refugees from abroad is now sending out climate refugees of its own. Since the beginning of the financial crisis, there has been a brain drain of monumental proportions. At the same time, the Greek economy is crying out for workers in the primary sector, in construction and tourism. But there are none. Purchasing power has plummeted below two-thirds of the European average. And we in Greece wonder why people are leaving. Among the EU 27 today, only Bulgaria ranks below Greece in purchasing power.

    As it celebrates its fiftieth anniversary, the Third Hellenic Republic is feeling exhausted—and the exhausted state of its democracy is certainly not an exclusively Greek affair. The institutions of accountability are withering. Parliamentary control is becoming inert. Independent authorities–once a great promise–are silenced when they do their job because they are a nuisance. The judiciary is faltering to the point of self-cancellation. The lack of pluralism in the press is shameful. Wiretaps have come to seem not scandalous but normal. For years to come, what is and what is not said (especially the latter) in the public sphere will not be the result of free will but the fruit of fear and blackmail. This is a nightmare.

    We, therefore, have good reason to doubt that the years to come will be happy for the Hellenic Republic, or for constitutional democracy in Europe as a whole.

    Predictions are overwhelmingly against an advancement towards consolidating and expanding democracy, both in the field of climate crisis management and in that of social justice and suffering institutions. This is not, however, an exclusively Greek phenomenon.

    It is probably the first time in the history of the EU that the Brussels bureaucracy stands embarrassed in the face of the overwhelming hegemony of the Right across Europe. After the European parliamentary elections of June 2024, the picture is even more frightening. The European Alt-Right now appears to be the most dynamic opposition to its neighboring pro-European Right; outside the Right there is little choice. Italy and France are leading the way. Greece is following.

    This situation fills democratically-minded people with despair. And for those of us who do not admit defeat, there is, above all, stress. Fatalism is less stressful, but it is not a solution. If there is no guaranteed happy end, as in the old Hollywood films, we can take some consolation from the fact that there is no end at all. The future, as Althusser said, lasts a long time.

    Dimitris Christopoulos is Professor in the Department of Political Science and History and Dean of the Political Sciences Faculty at Panteion University.

  • William Clare Roberts–Ideology and Self-Emancipation: Voluntary Servitude, False Consciousness, and the Career of Critical Social Theory

    William Clare Roberts–Ideology and Self-Emancipation: Voluntary Servitude, False Consciousness, and the Career of Critical Social Theory

    This article has been peer-reviewed for boundary 2 online. A response to this article can be viewed here

    William Clare Roberts–Ideology and self-emancipation: Voluntary servitude, false consciousness, and the career of critical social theory

     

    “Not a single class and not a single party can do without ideology, and the whole question is what its specific content is.”

    – “Orthodox”[1]

     

    1. Introduction

    Ideology is said in many ways. Too many ways. It is an inescapable word, but that is because it is used in a multitude of senses to name a dizzying array of phenomena.[2] It would be hubris to attempt to bring order to all of this literature. Nonetheless, there is one throughline in the history of ideology as a concept that is inescapable for any effort to rethink the radical politics of freedom, a project with some urgency today. If the north star of radical politics is universal emancipation from domination, and if the means of transport is the self-emancipation of the dominated, then navigating the question of voluntary servitude is inescapable.

    “Hereditary bondsmen! Know ye not / Who would be free themselves must strike the blow.” These lines are from Lord Byron’s Childe Harold’s Pilgrimage. When they were written, they urged on the Greek national struggle for independence from the Ottoman Empire. However, they soon traveled to other contexts and other struggles. They were taken up as a motto by Black abolitionists like Frederick Douglass, James McCune Smith, Henry Highland Garnet, and Martin R. Delaney. The lines “achieved great stature in antislavery discourse in part because they provided an essential point of reference in distinguishing between an orthodox abolitionism that awaited revolution from above and a heretical abolitionism that agitated for revolution from below” (Hickman 2016: 355).

    This dividing line ran not only through abolitionism but through nineteenth- and twentieth century political thought more generally. The Rules of the International Workingmen’s Association, drafted by Karl Marx in 1864, begin from the premise “that the emancipation of the working classes must be conquered by the working classes themselves.” Both Mikhail Bakunin and Errico Malatesta affirmed similar statements. A century later, Martin Luther King, Jr., the last great post-Hegelian political leader in the West, claimed that “freedom is never voluntarily given by the oppressor; it must be demanded by the oppressed.” This same conviction runs through anticolonial theorists and political activists, from Albert Memmi and Frantz Fanon to Walter Rodney and Steve Biko.[3] Biko, for instance, was forthright “that the blacks do not need a go-between in this struggle for their own emancipation” (2002: 25).

    What unites these claims is the intuition that freedom must be won, in some sense, by the unfree. And yet this political imperative has produced an array of theoretical perplexities and confusions. If the oppressed can emancipate themselves and are even under an obligation to do so, it is hard to account for why they are not already free without recourse to the paradoxical claim that the oppressed freely choose to be oppressed. And, indeed, this paradoxical claim has been articulated and insisted upon. Henry Highland Garnet, in his “Address to the Slaves of the United States,” proclaimed in no uncertain terms that “IT IS SINFUL IN THE EXTREME FOR YOU TO MAKE VOLUNTARY SUBMISSION” to the degrading conditions of enslavement (2001: 262).[4]

    Navigating this paradox of voluntary submission or voluntary servitude is one of the things that, historically, the theory of ideology has been supposed to do. Why, after all, would the oppressed and exploited, who generally outnumber, their oppressors and exploiters, often many times over, put up with such treatment? “If the people had understood their true interests, could any power or accident reduce them to the state they are now in?” (Benbow 1832: 6) Therefore, the people, who can and should emancipate themselves, must be preserved in their state of voluntary submission by “want of knowledge of their own worth and power,” an ignorance enforced by “the bonds of superstition and prejudice” and encouraged by the ruling classes who benefit therefrom (Benbow 1832: 5). This is the fount of the theory of ideology as a false consciousness that preserves domination. It is supposed to explain how self-emancipation, although it is within the power and in the interests of the oppressed, appears either impossible or undesirable. An epistemic barrier is all that stands in their way.

    The most commonly encountered version of the theory of ideology, however, is singularly ill-fitted to navigate anything at all. According to Ideology 101, the dominated have a material interest in overturning the society that oppresses them, but they are imbued with a false consciousness regarding their own interests. This false consciousness is due to a distorted representation of social relations that, by concealing the real nature of these relations, serves the interests of the dominant. Ideology exists because it is functionally beneficial for the ruling class, and it operates primarily either by legitimizing domination or by naturalizing it (or both). This makes alternative social arrangements unthinkable, thereby preventing self-emancipation.[5]

    An operationalized version of this account, aimed at a popular audience and geared towards political mobilization, claims that, “an ideology is an outlook that presents the interests of a powerful part of society as the universal interest, so that the whole of society will tend to see the interests of that part of society which the ideology primarily serves as their own interests.” Ideology is functional for the system of power insofar as it “systematically obscures and misrepresents our political agency,” or, alternately, insofar as it “institutionalises a worldview that legitimises the governing class and the way that class uses its control of the state’s power” (Ramsay 2022).

    This account of ideology is, I submit, worthless. It has no basis in any realistic analysis of exploitation or domination. It tells us nothing about the world of social power. It is no aid to emancipatory struggles of any sort. It is, basically, a junk drawer of broken claims and verbal tics, torn from any context that might give them meaning, and jumbled together without any regard for truth, sense, or utility.

    I am hardly the first person to notice that this traditional “concept of ideology has fallen into disrepute” (Cooke 2006: 4). It has been attacked by social theorists and philosophers and activists. Barrington Moore undermined it (1978). Andrea Dworkin undermined it (1983). It was attacked outright by Nicholas Abercrombie, Stephen Hill, and Bryan Turner, in a book widely credited with having destroyed it (1980). It was attacked by James Scott (1987). It was attacked again by James Scott (1990). It was attacked by Adam Przeworski (1985). It was given another book-length working over by Michael Rosen (1996), and now another book-length assault by Vivek Chibber (2022). Taking this up again might reasonably seem like mere necrohippoflagellation.

    However, the existing criticisms of the theory of ideology do not situate ideology in relation to the self-emancipation thesis.[6] Instead, they situate ideology as a problem within the study of social stability, or of protest and resistance, or of complicity and collaboration. Therefore, there is something hollow about the victories repeatedly won against this theoretical antagonist. Because the attacks on the theory of ideology have not located that theory within the practical problem that motivates it, these attacks have left those interested in self-emancipation with no recourse but to regenerate the theory of ideology. Its critics have provided no alternative.

    This essay attempts, therefore, to return ideology to the problem of self-emancipation, and thereby to bring some reasonable order to our judgments about the sense and utility of the word. It is historical in approach and constitutes a prolegomenon to the work of disentangling the living from the dead in twentieth century accounts of ideology.

    The basic story I tell is one of reasonable local interventions half-remembered and misappropriated, inserted into new contexts, and mutating further with every reinsertion. I identify three basic families of ideology-concepts, each of which interacts in its own way with the problem self-emancipation and with the idea of voluntary servitude. I begin by recalling what voluntary servitude meant prior to the invention of ideology, when it was part of both ancient and Renaissance aristocratic discourses (Section II). This prehistory already contains three elements that will be important to the later career of ideology: the notion of a second nature, the idea that consent can be manufactured, and the opposition between immediate interests and duty.

    The first account of ideology was proposed by the French liberal philosopher, Antoine Destutt de Tracy, and it was an Enlightenment project of social reform through pedagogy (Section III). This account was preserved intact when it was criticized as idealist and ineffective by Marx and Engels (Section IV). The aim of these sections is to locate a break between the pre-Marxist articulation of ideology, voluntary servitude, and emancipation – a pre-Marxist history which includes Marx and Engels – and the twentieth century career of ideology as a Marxist and post-Marxist category.

    Section V turns to two accounts of ideology that are Marxist in origin, but basically unrelated to Marx and Engels’s criticisms of Destutt de Tracy and all the other “ideologists.” Both Marxist accounts emerge from Lenin’s valorization of “ideological struggle” – agitation and organizing work around political grievances, tactical issues, and doctrinal disputes. One stream, flowing through Lukács and issuing in the Frankfurt School of critical theory, conceives ideology as a partial and therefore false consciousness of the social totality (Section VI). The other, flowing through Gramsci and Althusser before issuing in the work of Stuart Hall and Göran Therborn, conceives ideology as the institutional norms and discursive practices that pattern and elicit agency (Section VII).

    The conclusions of this historical reconstruction are mixed. In the negative column, the Lenin-Lukács-Frankfurt tradition of ideology critique is dead, and its soul has departed its body. The body – a certain political practice of communist morality – is in an advanced state of putrescence, breaking down continuously and giving off a stench. The soul has ascended to a higher plane of pure normativity, where it has all of the effective power you would expect in an incorporeal being. However, on the other side of the ledger, the Lenin-Gramsci-Althusser tradition of ideology theory provides important theoretical resources for analyzing social domination and struggles for self-emancipation among the dominated. Putting these resources to work should be the project of critical social theory.

     

    2. Voluntary servitude before ideology

    The notion of voluntary servitude predates by centuries both the theorization of ideology and the formulation of the self-emancipation thesis. In the first instance, voluntary servitude was a staple of Greek and Roman discourse. It was both recommended as a form of tutelage – if a young man could find a master/mentor who could make him better – and bemoaned as a tiresome wasting of one’s life “in a thankless attending upon the great” (Seneca 1932: 289). Regardless, it was a choice made – well or poorly – by a young man trying to make something of himself.

    In Plato’s Republic, Socrates claims that all who are unable to master themselves through philosophical self-discipline ought to serve a master who is able to do so. Everyone is ethically obligated to serve the mind, to be directed “by what is divine and prudent,” if not in one’s own soul then in the soul of another, “set over one from outside” (2016: 591c-d). This ethical obligation does not give to anyone a right to forcibly enslave another, however. It is not the business of the philosopher to capture and compel students or of a good man to hunt admirers. Recognition of and attendance upon a worthy master should be voluntary, and each should be “a seeker and a student of that study by which he might be able to learn and find out who will give him the capacity and the knowledge to distinguish the good and the bad life, and so everywhere and always to choose the better from among those that are possible” (2016: 618c).

    The ancient discourse circles around the task of choosing well your way of life and your role model, one who lives a paradigmatic life worth emulating. It does not address the forms of actual slavery that everywhere surround the mentor and mentee. Actual slavery, even when it is thought to be natural and beneficial to the enslaved (as in Aristotle, Philo, or Augustine), is premised on force and necessity. Slaves are either frankly acknowledged to be unwilling captives or are condescendingly understood as incapable of recognizing what is good for them.[7] Regardless, their bondage is not voluntary. Voluntary servitude and legally sanctioned domination did not overlap, therefore, even if the latter provided a fund of metaphors for speaking about the former.[8]

    When this ancient discourse was relaunched during the renaissance of the sixteenth century, however, forcible domination and voluntary servitude are seen to be much more closely linked. The two remain distinct, but are understood to interact causally. The basic schema is that the voluntary servitude of some enables the forcible domination of others. Chattel slavery has receded into the background of European experience, even as it is about to roar back to the center of the new Atlantic economy. Free cities are fewer and are not at the head of political organization, but adjuncts to kingly and papal courts. The two realms of the ancient world, the realm of free citizens and the realm of slaves, are not, therefore, massive social facts but inherited categories of thought. Instead of slavery, therefore, tyranny is the reference point.[9]

    Estienne de La Boétie’s Discourse on Voluntary Servitude, published posthumously by his friend, Michel de Montaigne, is an exemplary discussion in this respect. La Boétie sets himself the task of explaining “how it happens that so many men, so many towns, so many cities, so many nations at times tolerate a single tyrant who has no other power than what they grant him, who has no other power to harm them than inasmuch as they are willing to tolerate it, who could do ill to them only insofar as they would rather suffer it than oppose him” (2012: 2). This fact of political tyranny cannot be explained by the principles of either Ciceronian or Machiavellian statecraft. It makes no rational sense for so many to fear “a single puny man, and generally the most cowardly, effeminate one in the nation.” Nor can anyone love the one who subjects them to “pillage, lechery, cruelty,” who leaves them “with neither property, nor relations, wives, nor children, not even their lives belonging to them” (2012: 4). If neither love nor fear actuates tyranny, then some new principle of rule must be revealed.

    La Boétie proposes three: custom, trickery, and corruption.

    First, he argues that human beings are “denatured” by custom, which overwhelms our natural inclinations and teaches us to serve (2012: 11). However, this is obviously an inadequate answer to the puzzle. Custom can go either way. It can cultivate the desire for liberty – La Boétie points to the Venetians and the Spartans[10] – as well as the desire for a master. Thus, it is only for “men born under the yoke and then raised and nurtured in serfdom” that being “content to live as they were born, without looking any further,” entails servitude (2012: 13). Hence, we arrive at the real inadequacy of explaining servitude by reference to custom: it simply pushes the question back a step. How were free people ever subjected in the first place, such that they can become accustomed to servitude?

    Therefore, La Boétie advances a second argument. Most people, he claims, are credulous and easily tricked. “In truth, it is in the nature of the common people,” he claims, “to be suspicious of those who love them and gullible towards those who fool them.”

    You should not imagine that there is any bird more easily taken in by a decoy, or any fish swallows the hook more rapidly for an appetizing worm, than all people are quickly tempted into servitude by the slightest lure that is passed before their mouths, as they say; it is amazing how quickly they let themselves go if only you titillate them. Plays, games, street-shows, spectacles, gladiators, strange beasts, medallions, tableaus, and other such merchandise were for people in ancient times the bait of servitude, the price of their liberty, the instruments of tyranny. (2012: 23)

    Both of these arguments, however, apply only to the common run of people. They are easily fooled into giving up their freedom, and easily trained to bear the yoke of servitude. But these methods “work for tyrants only with lower-class, common folk” (La Boétie 2012: 29). There is always a minority, “better born than the others, who feel the weight of the yoke and cannot help shaking it, who never grow used to subjection” (2012: 17). For these few, “servitude is not to their taste, no matter how it is dressed up” (2012: 18).

    Nonetheless, La Boétie seems to think that even the better sort of people are susceptible to certain inducements, even when they are “well-armed” and “can carry out some action” (2012: 30). How so?

    This subject occupies the last portion of La Boétie’s essay, and he calls it “the source and secret of domination, the basis and foundation of tyranny” (2012: 30). This secret is, in brief, that those who cannot be tricked or trained can still often be corrupted by material interests. Thus, “there are almost as many for whom tyranny seems to profit as those for whom liberty would be agreeable,” and, through “patronage or sub-patronage,” the tyrant is able to draw to him those who “want to serve in order to have possessions” (2012: 31, 33).

    The tyrant thus enslaves some of his subjects by means of the others, and is guarded by those of whom he himself ought to be wary if they were worth anything: as they say, to split wood he uses wedges of the wood itself. So here are his archers, here are his guards, here are his halberdiers – not that they themselves do not suffer at times from him, but these poor souls, abandoned by God and men, are content to endure ill in order to do ill, not to the one who does it to them, but to those who endure it as they do and can do nothing about it. (La Boétie 2012: 32)

    These are the real “voluntary servants” of the Discourse’s title: those who willingly submit to a tyrant in order to enjoy the plunder and enforce the misrule.[11]

    La Boétie claims they are making a fool’s bargain. They cannot really possess anything so long as the one they serve has the power to take it all away whenever they wish (2012: 33). Nor can they really count on the tyrant’s love and friendship – a tyrant, by his nature, does not know “the best thing to do” and “never either is loved or himself loves” (2012: 35). Even if they escape their lord’s fickle willfulness and suspicion of those closest at hand, these accomplices will be destroyed by the tyrant’s successor and hated by the people, and “the names of these ‘people-eaters’” will be “blackened by the ink of countless quills and their reputations torn apart in countless books” (2012: 38). Therefore, while these ‘better sorts’ of servants may not be fooled by the tyrant’s tricks, they fool themselves. And so La Boétie end with a plea to his readers to “learn to do good,” so as not to become “accomplices” to tyrants (2012: 38).

    In La Boétie’s three principles of subjection one can discern three great hypotheses of Enlightenment political thought. First, that culture is a second nature, leading people to act in ways that cannot be understood as following from our rational nature. Secondly, that consent can be manufactured through the skillful manipulation of images and distractions. Finally, that economic interests rule all, and that (almost) everyone and everything has their price.

    None of these, however, amount to the idea that an individual voluntarily gives to another the power to dominate them. Despite La Boétie’s rhetoric, these principles all operate via contrasts between one and many, self and other: a few give the tyrant the means to dominate the many, we give the tyrant the power to dominate others, they give the tyrant the power to dominate us. The consequence may be that the people considered in toto seem to give to the tyrant the power to dominate the people in toto, but this looks more like a fallacy of composition than like a valid diagnosis.

    This is hardly fatal to the argument, however, since La Boétie’s discourse is aimed at the conscience of the nobleman. It is not supposed to be a general social theory of domination, but a call to be a certain sort of person: incorruptible, public spirited, upright. It appeals to those like the author himself. Indeed, since La Boétie made no move to publish his discourse, it might best be read as an appeal to the author himself. Its mode of address hovers between ethical exhortation and meditation. It recalls to the reader/writer the many temptations that would lure him from the straight path, and the punishments – spiritual and social – that would befall him were he to stay.

    Within this ethical mode of discourse the fate of all depends upon the virtue of each. At least among the nobility. The causal order obtaining between voluntary servitude and slavery to the despot runs from the top down. The voluntary servitude of “four or five”[12] secures the cord by which “a hundred thousand, and even millions,” are bound to the tyrant. In the ancient picture, the massive foundation of slavery and other forms of bonded labor made possible the sphere in which a few free men might make themselves the voluntary servants of worthy (or unworthy) mentors. There is conditioning here, and possibility, but not causality. In the post-Machiavellian and humanistic tradition of Montaigne and La Boétie, a causal relation obtains between forcible bondage and voluntary servitude, but it runs in exactly the opposite direction: the voluntary servitude of a few leisured men brings about the enslavement of the mass of the people.

    “But where the danger lies, also grows the saving power.” The fundamentally aristocratic thrust of La Boétie’s discourse is rooted less in its disdain for the “lower-class, common folk” than in its exclusive attention to the actions and inclinations of these few, who can decide the fate of a nation. It may well be necessary to flatter those with wealth, land, and proximity to political power, to inflate for them their own importance to the commonwealth, so as to impress upon them a sense of noblesse oblige. It does not, however, make for either a very exacting social theory or anything like a radical commitment to self-emancipation.[13]

     

    3. Ideology before ideology critique

    “Ideology,” as a term, was coined in 1796 by one of the scholars and scientists grouped under the new Institut de France. Antoine Louis Claude Destutt, compte de Tracy, presented works on the moral and political sciences to his colleagues at the Institute, works which grew into his Elements of Ideology (1801-15). In content, little seems to unite the writings of Destutt de Tracy with La Boétie’s Discourse on Voluntary Servitude. In his Elements, Destutt de Tracy tried to rigorously deduce a canon of probabilistic reasoning, a sentimentalist moral theory, and a liberal political economy from empiricist epistemological premises. Presented in a thoroughly didactic style, and intended to form the basis of a system of universal pedagogy, Destutt de Tracy’s writings are in almost every way contrary in spirit to La Boétie’s intensely private essay.

    Nonetheless, Destutt de Tracy develops the central themes of La Boétie’s discourse – culture as a second nature, the manufacture of consent, and the rule of interests – and it makes sense to read his Elements as a belated and unintended answer to La Boétie. Like La Boétie, Destutt de Tracy attempts to understand the denaturalization of humanity, how we fall away from our original condition, in which we are free and enjoy an error-free apprehension of our world. Universalizing La Boétie’s picture of the “lower-class, common folk,” Destutt de Tracy constructs a model of the person as a desiring machine, amenable to behavioral modification. And like his predecessor, he posits an unstable and problematic distinction between desires and interests, between what motivates us and what ought to motivate us.

    To put it baldly, ideology does not name, for Destutt de Tracy, the problem of voluntary servitude, but rather the solution to that problem. Destutt de Tracy used the term ideology to name a new science of ideas, one that would “give a complete knowledge of our intellectual faculties” and allow us “to deduce from that knowledge the first principles of all the other branches of our knowledge” (2011: 9). The goal was “really to place the moral and political sciences on their true basis, a knowledge of our intellectual faculties” (2011: 10). The most important consequences are the ones “which will experience the greatest opposition”: that “the great rural proprietors … are but lenders of money, burdensome to agriculture;” that “the idle rich … are absolutely good for nothing;” and that “the true interests of the poor are exactly the same as the true interest of the whole society” (2011: 255).

    To convince the wealthy proprietors of these results, it is necessary not so much to oppose their interests – “well or ill understood” – as to overcome their passions, and especially their “vanity,” “the most violent and antisocial” of all the passions:

    On many occasions, then, it is still more difficult to conciliate to truth than to discover it. … We have perceived, and said, that we should know well the consequences of our actions, to appreciate justly, the merit or demerit of the sentiments which urge us to this or that action; and now we see that it is necessary to analyze our sentiments themselves, submit them to a rigorous examination, distinguish those which being founded on just judgments always direct us well, and those which having their source in illusions, and rising from the obliquities of our minds, cannot fail to lead us astray and form within us a false and blind consciousness [une fausse et aveugle conscience], which always removes us further from the road of reason, the only one leading to happiness. (2011: 255)[14]

    Thus, the project of ideology is, by the methodical investigation of the origin and train of our ideas, to overcome the false consciousness which can arise from a peculiar cast of mind and its attendant illusions. This false consciousness, by diverting people from the rational path, leads them to unhappiness, and nowhere more so than where “they employ the species of laborers the worst paid, namely slaves” (Destutt de Tracy 2011: 182). Moral corruption follows from epistemic faults.

    Whereas La Boétie began from the natural liberty of human beings, and set out to explain how such creatures, “born not only in possession of our freedom, but with a desire to defend it” can be so “denatured” as to “lose the memory of [our] original being, and the desire to regain it” (2012: 9, 11), Destutt de Tracy begins from the natural truthfulness of our perceptions, which “are all of them always such as we feel them, and are not susceptible to error, taken each separately, and in itself” (2011: 34). From this beginning, he does not so much desire to explain how we come to be mired in error, confusion, and false beliefs – how we fall into error is easily comprehended, he thinks – but to establish a set of practices by which we might recall ourselves to the truthful comprehension of what we experience and preserve our judgments in this truth by methodical proceedings.

    However, the fact that we do find ourselves enmeshed in error, despite the fact that “all our perceptions are originally just and true,” can only be the consequence of “admi[ting] an element which is opposed to” our original perceptions, “which denaturalizes and changes them, without our perceiving it” (Destutt de Tracy 2011: 36). For La Boétie, as we have seen, most people are easily lured to their doom by enticements. For Destutt de Tracy, the very basis of our personality is our experience of preferring one thing to another, which is nothing other than our will. This faculty of preference is primitively manifested in desire. In fact, Destutt de Tracy “give[s] indifferently the name of desire or of will to all the acts of this faculty.” “It is solely because we perform such acts,” he continues, “that we have the ideas of personality and of property” (2011: 67). The faculty of preference is both the basis of personality and the reason we are simple recording devices, accumulating true perceptions of the world around us. Desire leads us into error.

    Unlike La Boétie, however, Destutt de Tracy does not wish to denigrate the desires of the masses, but to satisfy them. He maintains repeatedly that “every desire is a need[15]  and that we have both a right to satisfy all our needs and a duty to do so as expeditiously and effectively as we can, given whatever powers we possess. This duty is modified in unspecified ways by the ability we have to communicate with one another and to thereby enter into conventions, but our one general duty “of well employing our means” remains intact (Destutt de Tracy 2011: 90). Hence, we all face the situation in which we must pursue the satisfaction of our needs in a world of other sentient beings striving to do the same, and “as they act in consequence of their will it is [our] duty to conciliate or subjugate that will in order to bring them to contribute to the satisfaction of our desires” (2011: 84). And they have the same duty vis-à-vis us.

    This is the basis of Destutt de Tracy’s liberal political economy, which is premised on the notion that a free and open labor market will conduce to the highest wages possible, and to the greatest general prosperity. He presumes that we are potentially very useful to one another, and that we can both generate and enjoy far more wealth if we cooperate with one another. For this reason, it is more efficacious to conciliate the wills of others than to subjugate them. This conciliation of the wills of others is nothing but society itself, and it consists in the offering to others of what they need in exchange for their assistance in acquiring what we need ourselves. “Commerce is the whole of society, as labor is the whole of riches,” and the benefits of the former – “concurrence of force, increase and preservation of knowledge, and division of labor” – show themselves in the immense augmentation of the power and extent of the latter (Destutt de Tracy 2011: 101–2).

    Despite Destutt de Tracy’s equation of desire and need, however, he also admits that not every desire “is founded on a real need, that is to say on a just sentiment of our true interest” (2011: 68). This separation between a need – which every desire is – and a real need is tricky. As he continues, “we have also often real needs without experiencing desires; in this sense that many things are often very necessary to our greater well being, and even to our preservation, without our perceiving it, and consequently without our desiring them” (2011: 68). He brings forward the example of the internal workings of our bodies in holding off sickness, but he also gestures towards “all the combinations which take place in … the moral order, without our being aware of, or without our foreseeing, the consequences” (2011: 68–69). Here we might consider all manner of social dynamics and institutions. They may really benefit (or harm) us without us being able to perceive our reliance upon (or injury by) them. Thus, we might need – really need – them (or their removal), but without desiring them (or their removal). The opaque complexity of the social world – the fact that what is available to our immediate perception is given by and dependent upon indefinitely ramifying interactions and processes and relations that recede from inspection – makes it necessary that we need what we cannot desire.

    Despite this recognition of social opacity, Destutt de Tracy claims immediately thereafter that “every actual need is a desire,” and that “we may lay it down as a general thesis, that our desires are the source of all our needs, none of which would exist without them” (2011: 69). These are hardly identical claims. One can appreciate that, yes, even real needs of which we are unaware and hence undesiring find their source of their needfulness in our desires: we need these “combinations in the moral order,” for instance, in order to satisfy the desires we feel using the powers we have. All manner of social infrastructure has the character of not necessarily being an object of desire, while yet being in service of desire. I may hate the presence of train tracks in my neighborhood, even though those tracks are used by trains supplying the produce I buy at the market. Nonetheless, Destutt de Tracy’s claim that every real need is a desire seems flatly contradicted by his own argument (and by a great deal of evidence, besides).

    This contradiction is the key to understanding ideology as a program not simply for research but for systematic pedagogy. Ideology as a science of sensations issues in liberal political economy because, without doing away with social opacity, political economy provides assurances that this opacity is irrelevant. Every other person is situated just as we are, and every other person’s desires are also needs. So long as we have faith that every interaction is a voluntary social exchange, we have evidence of what we cannot see. The invisible hand undergirds or guarantees “the difficult virtue of minding your own business,” as Gerald Gaus has formulated the liberal ethical ideal, by making the contradiction between social opacity and self-transparency irrelevant for practical purposes (1997).[16]

    On Gaus’s understanding, “Liberal society can only exist if, rather than making the doings of mankind or my neighbour my business, I acknowledge that no one is bound to enter my way of living unless I can appeal to his interests, however broadly defined” (1997: 2). As Gaus recognizes, this self-restraint on my part is only practically possible if “individuals are understood to be morally autonomous in the sense that they can put aside their fantasies, perversities or foolish notions and respect the legal personality of others, and are properly held morally accountable if they fail to do so” (1997).

    Ideology was an attempt to teach people to be morally autonomous in this sense, but also, crucially, to teach people that others are morally autonomous in this sense, and that society among such morally autonomous individuals takes the exclusive form of commerce. Each of these premises supports and depends upon the others, and the logical structure that emerges is, like all triangular constructions, very stable and robust.

    Ideology sought, then, to overcome vanity by teaching that every other is exactly like myself, to overcome passion by teaching that my desires will be best satisfied by my satisfying the desires of others, and to overcome illusion and false consciousness by teaching that every voluntary transaction is mutually beneficial. Ideology overcomes voluntary servitude by generalizing it, transmuting corruption into rectitude in much the same way as Mandeville transmuted private vices into public benefits. The pyramid of dependency, by which a whole nation is made to subserve the interests of one man, is destroyed by being fractalized. We all depend on others – and most especially on the capitalists – and this all-around dependency entails that, by means of commerce, we each subserve the interests of all.

     

    4. The first ideology critique

    It has become something of a commonplace that between Destutt de Tracy and Marx, the meaning of “ideology” underwent a reversal, and that Napoleon Bonaparte was the primary agent of this reversal.

    The thesis of reversal is very wide-spread. Terry Eagleton claims that “Ideology, which in the hands of Marx and Engels will shortly come to denote the illusion that ideas are somehow autonomous of the material world, starts life [in Destutt de Tracy] as exactly the reverse: as one branch of a mechanical materialism which clings to the faith that the operations of the mind are as predictable as the laws of gravity” (1991, 66). Michael Rosen finds it “surprising and ironic” that between Destutt de Tracy and Marx there is an “apparent reversal in the meaning of the term,” such that what was once a French term of approbation for “a positive approach to the study of ideas in society” became a term of abuse for German idealism (1996: 170–71). Michael Freeden also portrays Marx and Engels as reversing the meaning of ideology along similar lines; from being a project “very much in line with the positivist movement in 19th century France,” ideology became, in the hands of Marx and Engels, a criticism of “the spiritual and romantic nature of German idealist thought,” which “attributed independent existence to ideas, thought, and consciousness” (2003: 4–5). George Lichtheim, in a classic essay that set the terms for much of the academic discussion of the history of ideology as a concept, did not go so far as to call Marx and Engels’s conception the reverse of Destutt de Tracy’s, but did insist that “the Marxian concept of ideology … from the start has a meaning different from that which it had for his eighteenth-century predecessors,” a difference that “reflects a clear awareness of the devaluation [the term ‘ideology’] had meanwhile undergone” (1965: 175, incl. n. 37).

    That Napoleon is responsible for this reversal in sense is almost as widely asserted. Eagleton claims that it is with Napoleon that ideology “shifts from denoting a sceptical scientific materialism to signifying a sphere of abstract, disconnected ideas; and it is this meaning of the word which will then be taken up by Marx and Engels” (1991: 70). Jan Rehmann criticizes Eagleton for “overstat[ing] the continuity” between Napoleon’s attacks on the idéologues and Marx and Engels’s critical conception of ideology, but admits, “to be sure,” that the latter “tapped into (and were dependent on) the given semantic field that had been prepared by Napoleon’s attacks” (2014: 20).[17] Moreover, precisely where he identifies “similarities between the project of the idéologistes and of Marx” – in “a common interest in the critical analysis of ideas and images, the conditions in which they emerged, and their modes of functioning” – we can see that Rehmann presupposes the reversal of sense (2014: 20). For Destutt de Tracy, the critical analysis of ideas and images was ideology, whereas for Marx and Engels ideology named the “ideas and images” subject to critical analysis.

    This commonplace story is, I think, almost entirely fiction. Yes, Bonaparte attacked Destutt de Tracy and his fellows, and made idéologue into a term of abuse for abstract and metaphysical thought. Yes, Marx grew up with this use of the term, and used the term this way in some of his earliest writings. But when Marx and Engels attacked “the German ideology,” they were, on the whole, using the term just as Destutt de Tracy used it, to name the effort to overcome illusions and false consciousness by means of rational argumentation.

    The sense that there is a reversal here is explicable simply by the fact that Marx and Engels think the ideological project is ridiculous. The sense that they have picked up Napoleon’s use of the term is explicable by the fact that they associate this ideological project with the educators of humanity – “lawyers, politicians (statesmen in general), moralists, monastics” (Marx and Engels 2017, I/5: 120) – and their “occupational hazard” of exaggerating their own efficacy and independence, and by extension, of exaggerating the causal efficacy and independence of laws, speeches, arguments, and sermons.[18]

    The continuity between Destutt de Tracy and Marx and Engels on the meaning of “ideology” is less surprising when one realizes that Marx had read – and copied out several pages of extracts from – the Traité de la Volonté in mid-1844, when he was living in Paris.[19] Marx and Engels were quite explicit about the purpose of their polemics against German philosophy and German socialism in 1845-46. In the text published as a “Preface” to The German Ideology,[20] Marx wrote:

    People have always had false notions [falsche Vorstellungen] about themselves, about what they are and what they should be. They have set up their circumstances according to their notions of God, of normal people, etc. The monstrosities born of their brains have burst from their heads. They, the creators, bowed before their creatures. Let us free them from the fantasies, the ideas, the dogmas, the imaginary beings under whose yoke they waste away. Let us rebel against this domination of thought. Let us teach them to exchange these imaginings for thoughts that correspond to human nature, says one, to behave critically towards them, says the other, to put them out of their heads, says the third, and – existing reality will collapse.

    These innocent and childish fantasies form the kernel of the modern Young Hegelian philosophy, which in Germany is not only received with horror and awe by the public, but is also presented by our philosophical heroes themselves with the solemn consciousness of its world-shattering dangerousness and criminal ruthlessness. The purpose of the first volume of this publication is to unmask these sheep, who take themselves and are taken for wolves, to show how they only bleat out philosophically the notions of the German Bürger, how the boasts of these philosophical interpreters only reflect the wretchedness of actual German conditions. (2017, I/5: 3)

    In a crossed-out addendum to this text, Marx added, “There is no specific difference between German idealism and the ideology of all other peoples. These, too, regard the world as dominated by ideas, ideas or concepts as the defining principles, and definite thoughts as the mystery of the material world accessible to the philosophers” (2017, I/5: 804).

    As we have seen, this is a fair, if sarcastic characterization of Destutt de Tracy’s pedagogical project. Marx is claiming that he Young Hegelians are engaged in a “German ideology,” very much akin to the French original. They wish to overcome illusions and false consciousness by means of rational criticism, by teaching Germans to abandon the “falsche Vorstellungen” that dominate their lives. The critique of ideology leveled by Marx and Engels, then, assimilates the German ideology to Destutt de Tracy’s ideology and criticizes both as forms of superstructure idealism (Mills 1992), the false belief that religious, intellectual, and political practices of discursive production have an independent and decisive causal power.

    This critical appropriation of Destutt de Tracy’s term of art has caused immense confusion. Therefore, Paul Bowman has proposed referring to Marx and Engels’s critical concept as protagonism in order to differentiate it from the many other senses in which “ideology” has been used both within and outside Marxist traditions (2021). According to Bowman’s usage, protagonism names, narrowly, “the presumption that the state (or more precisely, the ideological superstructure) is where social change happens,” and, more broadly, “the (idealistic) delusion that the ideas of the ideological classes, the ideas which they fool themselves are the motives for the decisions they make, are the decisive force in historical agency” (2021). I will henceforth adopt Bowman’s convention for the sake of referring specifically to the object of Marx and Engels’s critique, and refer to protagonism-ideology.[21]

    Marx and Engels understand protagonism-ideology, generally, as the attempt to remake the world either by force of words or so as to make it live up to an ideal. Their belief that protagonism-ideology is misguided is grounded in their “sociological materialism” (Mills 1992). Practices of production, exploitation, and domination are, on this view, causally prior to and effective apart from religious, intellectual, and political practices of discursive production, howsoever these latter are institutionalized. The types of speech acts that human communities can engage in are, broadly speaking, conditioned by the basic practices of material production that allow these communities to reproduce their existence. These practices of community reproduction always involve definite forms of social interaction among community members. Hunter-gatherer societies cannot support a complex social division of labor, for example, and no leisured priest class can arise where there is no developed division of labor.

    This view does not deny that political ideas, religious myths, or intellectual theories can be causally effective in altering the social world. Marx and Engels spent their lives producing political ideas and intellectual theories in an attempt to change the social world, and it would be odd if they thought that their own project was impossible. Rather, their materialism specifies how discursive practices can be effective. The only way that ideas, myths, and theories can effectively transform society is by changing the form of material production and the forms of exploitation and domination that attend it. Institutionalized discursive practices like the modern system of research universities rely upon a highly-developed division of labor and a large economic surplus, but they also help to produce those things. Societies that can support such university systems realize gains in economic productivity and military defense capability that give them a competitive advantage against other forms of social organization.[22] But societies that can support complex systems of discourse production can also support a plethora of materially useless discourse production. This development encourages protagonism-ideology, since discourse producers in such societies will predictably be inclined to think of themselves as more than ornamental decorations on the surface of society.

    The ur-type of protagonism-ideology, for Marx, was the liberal ideology he encountered in Destutt de Tracy. It sought, as we have seen, to remake the world by teaching people how to mind their own business. As a social reform project grounded in an ethical project of self-scrutiny and rational self-improvement, ideology is an obvious paradigm for protagonism. But it is also paradigmatic in that it sought to make the social world live up to an ideal of mutually-beneficial voluntary interaction which is itself derived, via abstraction, from concrete practices of market exchange.

    Marx and Engels’s criticism of protagonism-ideology has little to do with what came to be called ideology critique, and just as little to do with the problem of voluntary servitude. Marx and Engels did think that Feuerbach, Bauer, Stirner, and company, had incorrect and confused ideas. But they did not think that these ideas concealed the real nature of German social relations, except in the banal sense that Feuerbach, Bauer, Stirner, and company were so preoccupied by their arguments with one another that they did not take the time or effort to investigate the real nature of German social relations. Neither did their ideas serve the interests of the dominant; they served only their own interest in inflating the theorists’ own importance.

    Nowhere do Marx and Engels suggest that the German ideology is functionally beneficial for the German ruling class. On the contrary, they suggest that it is functionally useless. The German ideology is not a barrier to the self-emancipation of the German people, for the simple reason that if it were a barrier then the German ideology would be correct, and Marx and Engels’s whole point is that the German ideology is not correct. It is the German ideology itself that claims that incorrect ideas are a barrier to self-emancipation. This is the position Marx and Engels are mocking in the “German ideology” manuscripts. It is not their own position.

    The claim that is most often pointed to as warrant for the notion that Marx and Engels subscribe to the dominant ideology thesis is their claim that, “The thoughts of the dominant class are in every epoch the dominant thoughts, i.e. the class which is the dominant material power in society is at the same time its dominant intellectual power” (2017, I/5: 60). However, this passage only seems to support the usual conclusion insofar as readers take the conclusion for granted in reading the sentence. There are two aspects to the problem. First, people assume that “the dominant thoughts” are equivalent to “ideology.”[23] Second, they assume that Marx and Engels are claiming that the thoughts of the dominant class are “the dominant thoughts” in the sense of being mental shackles, preventing the subordinate classes from freeing themselves. Neither assumption is warranted.

    Read next to the prefatory text, the reference to “the dominant thoughts” of the epoch obviously echoes the philosophical heroes’ demand, “Let us rebel against this domination of thoughts.” The ruling ideas are not ideology. Rather, the notion that there are ruling ideas is basic to protagonism-ideology itself. Marx and Engels are deflating this protagonist-ideological notion by translating it into the materialist equivalent, “the thoughts of the dominant class.” The entire passage surrounding the oft-quoted sentence follows through on this claim by asserting that the dominant class in any society derives its ideas about itself, those it dominates, and the world in general, from its social situation. Its thoughts are “the ideal expression of the dominant material conditions, the dominant material conditions conceived as thoughts,” and so it makes no sense to act “as if the dominant thoughts were not the thoughts of the dominant class and had a power distinct from the power of that class” (2017, I/5: 60–61).

    Marx and Engels’s critique of ideology is on this point: ideologists act as if the dominant ideas were something other than the ideas of the dominant and had a power apart from the power of the dominant class. Ideology names a naive approach to the dominant ideas, and approach that “detaches the thoughts of the ruling class from the ruling class,” “makes them independent,” and then “remains stuck with the fact that in one epoch these and those thoughts dominated without worrying about the conditions of production of and about the producers of these thoughts” (2017, I/5: 62). This is the “delusion of the ideologists,” and it is based in “the division of labor” (2017, I/5: 63), as Mills has argued (1992). Because of its social origin, ideology is itself usually among “the ruling ideas.” “The dominant class itself, on average, imagines” that its ideas are dominant because of their own power (Marx and Engels 2017, I/5: 62). This underscores, however, that ideology, from Marx and Engels, is not another name for “the ruling ideas.” Ideology is an idea commonly encountered among the dominant: the idea that the world is ruled by ideas, and a pedagogical project expressing that idea as a plan for general enlightenment.

    The second assumption readers bring to this text is that, in some sense, “the ruling ideas” rule over the minds of the subordinate classes, acting as a barrier to their self-emancipation. In the words of Amy Wendling, they “organize our thinking,” and “wield, by virtue of this fact, a great deal of political power” (2012: xii). However, as we have already seen, this is what Marx and Engels are denying in this passage. The power of the dominant ideas is nothing but the power of the dominant class; there is no independent political power of ideas. But, one might object, how then are we to understand Marx and Engels’s claim that “the thoughts of those who lack the means of intellectual production are subordinate” to the thoughts of the dominant class? Or their claim that the members of the dominant class dominate also “as thinkers, as producers of thoughts, and regulate the production and distribution of the thoughts of their time”? (2017, I/5: 60)

    I think the best way to read these passages is as implying a fairly prosaic claim about the production and distribution of texts and the like. This is in keeping with the polemically materialist character of the entire manuscript, in which “spirit” is derived from its beginnings in “agitated layers of air, sounds” (2017, I/5: 30). The regulation of thought by the dominant is the regulation of the printing presses, the libraries, the universities, etc., and nothing more. The subordination of the thought of the dominated is the subjection of their speech and writing to censorship, prohibition, illiteracy, and the stultification produced by a life of labor under conditions which allow for few letters. That Marx and Engels are not thinking of anything more than this is indicated, above all, by the fact that they never deny the emergence of revolutionary thought. This emergence is subject to the same condition as is the thought of the dominant class: a basis in the social production of life. “The existence of revolutionary thoughts in a particular epoch,” they write, “already presupposes the existence of a revolutionary class” (2017, I/5: 61–62).

    The ruling ideas are not ideology, and neither are they “a useful weapon of class rule” (Rudé 1980: 17). They are merely indicators of who rules and how, signs to be deciphered. The notion that a crucial part of class domination consists in the dominant class “imposing its own fantasies and ‘false reality’ on the subject class” is not, therefore, a Marxian or Engelsian notion at all. Neither is the notion that, “to end its subjection and break through the ‘false reality’ that capitalism had imposed on it, the proletariat … must develop a ‘true’ consciousness, or class consciousness, peculiar to itself” (Rudé 1980: 17). According to Marx and Engels, protagonism-ideology is an ineffectual and mystified attempt at self-emancipation. It puts into practice the belief that servitude is voluntary because servitude is primarily in the head, that education is the primary means of freeing the mind, and that the rest will follow. Marx and Engels’s critique of ideology is precisely that servitude is not voluntary but necessary, not in the head but in the reproduction of life. It is not underpinned by the “second nature” of the superstructure, but is rooted in the nature of society as the interdependent production and reproduction of human life. Humans are not born free and in the truth, but are born into a bondage from which we might work ourselves to freedom only by a transformation of the material basis of the social world.

    Even though it is not what Marx and Engels meant by ideology, however, I think the notion of a false consciousness that impedes the self-emancipation of the oppressed classes is a natural outgrowth of the Marxist project. This is not due to any argument Marx or Engels made, but due to the fact that the false consciousness thesis is a natural outgrowth of any politics oriented by self-emancipation. Marxism just happens to be the most influential political project of that sort, the project that seeded a hundred other movements with language, analyses, and bit of received revolutionary wisdom.

    In order to trace the emergence of false consciousness, we must turn to Leninism, the point at which Marxism grappled with the special collective action problems involved in self-emancipation and formulated, even before it was named, the concept of false-consciousness. The practical problems confronted by a Marxist politics of self-emancipation generated a concept of “ideological false consciousness,” which then came to be associated – retrospectively and incorrectly – with Marx and Engels’s employment of the terms “ideology” and “false consciousness.” This procedure – finding a textual hook in Marx and Engels’s writings to hang a practical problem on – ended up generating a truly perverse result: the tradition of ideology critique born from the Marxist tradition is a perfect example of the protagonism Marx and Engels criticized in the original ideology.

     

    5. The birth of false consciousness

    Lenin has become synonymous with vanguardism, substitutionism, and the replacement of democracy by party discipline, but he was as committed a partisan of self-emancipation as the world has seen. This contention will raise some eyebrows. The image of Lenin as dictator and planner extraordinaire is deeply ingrained. James Scott is echoing received wisdom when he associates Lenin with a “design for the construction of the revolution” every bit as authoritarian and “high-modernist” as “Le Corbusier’s design for the construction of the modern city” (2008: 147). Like an architect’s designs, Scott claims, Lenin’s plans are to be realized in the “inert materials” of “‘the masses’ or ‘the proletariat,’” who seem to bring nothing “to the revolutionary project beyond the raw material they represent” (2008: 154–55).

    The basis of Scott’s interpretation is Lenin’s What Is to Be Done?, written in 1903. The answer to the titular question of Lenin’s pamphlet is to build “an all-Russian political newspaper.” This should already be a hint that Scott’s understanding of Lenin is a bit odd. How does a plan for a political newspaper amount to a “design for the construction of a revolution”?[24] But, of course, Scott is building on a well-established tradition of portraying Lenin – and What Is to Be Done? in particular – as concerned above all with “the issue of the masses’ political inertia” (Ascher 1988: 37). Lenin is actually concerned, however, with precisely the opposite: the inertia of self-proclaimed revolutionaries in the face of a spontaneous uprising by the workers and peasants of Russia. It is the masses’ activity – far in advance of anything revolutionary activists can muster – that provokes Lenin to articulate the matrix of the theory of ideology as false consciousness: the necessity of ideological struggle. Lenin’s idea and practice of ideological struggle is what provokes the two classic formulations of the relationship between ideology and self-emancipation, the class-consciousness theory of Lukács and the hegemony theory of Gramsci.

    György Lukács, in History and Class Consciousness, made the absence of a correct ideology into the only obstacle standing between the proletariat and complete emancipation, and this became the inspiration for a conception of false consciousness as normative error, which would be developed by the Frankfurt School of critical theory, until it finally petered out in the Habermasian notion of performative contradiction. Three years after Lukács’s book, Antonio Gramsci was imprisoned by the fascist government of Italy. In prison, reflecting on Lenin’s revolutionary practice, he would develop his own account of hegemony, according to which the dominant class is able to secure the resignation, distraction, and even consent of the dominated to the extent that it is able to provide – or portray itself convincingly as providing – fairly steady material gains and to buy the active support of “bystander” groups in society. This account, as close as one can get to a macro-social development of La Boétie’s conception of voluntary servitude, was supplemented by Althusser’s understanding of the recruitment of individuals into forms of agency, and has given rise to a much more promising approach to ideology. The present section will develop Lenin’s understanding of ideological conflict, and the following sections will show how it was interpreted by Lukács as a theory of class consciousness, how this model descended into the ideology critique of the Frankfurt School, and how the Gramscian-Althusserian line of interpretation provides an alternative.

    It is crucial to remember that Marxists of Lenin’s generation had no access to the manuscripts on “the German ideology,” which were sitting in a box in SPD archives from the death of Engels until David Ryazonov found them in 1923. Ryazonov published parts of the manuscripts in 1926,[25] and the entirety of them, as Die deutsche Ideologie, in 1932 (Johnson 2022: 144–45). Thus, the formulators of the theory of ideology as false consciousness had no access to Marx and Engels’s discussion of ideology as superstructure idealism or protagonism. Lenin never saw these texts. Lukács published History and Class Consciousness just as Ryazonov was discovering them. Gramsci went into prison just as the first portions were published in German.

    Therefore, when these authors discuss ideology, they are basing their use of the word almost entirely on Marx’s two uses in the 1859 Preface to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, two uses in the Manifesto, one use in The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, and five uses in Capital, together with Engels’s more substantial discussion in Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German Philosophy. This goes a long way towards explaining the almost complete disconnect between Marx and Engels’s use of the term and the Marxist and post-Marxist debates about the theory of ideology.

    Of particular importance was Marx’s claim in the 1859 Preface that, with regard to periods of social revolution, “it is always necessary to distinguish between the material transformation of the economic conditions of production, which can be determined with the precision of natural science, and the legal, political, religious, artistic or philosophic – in short, ideological forms in which men become conscious of this conflict and fight it out.” The first thing that Gramsci did in his prison notebooks was to translate two short texts of Marx into Italian: the “Theses on Feuerbach” and the 1859 Preface.[26] In his translation of the line above, as Jan Rehmann notes, Gramsci translated “ideological forms in which men become conscious of this conflict and fight it out” as “ideological forms on which terrain [nel cui terreno] men become conscious of this conflict and fight it out” (2014: 118). According to Rehmann, this signals Gramsci’s refusal to treat ideologies as “mere forms of consciousness,” and his commitment to the notion that ideologies are “an ‘objective and effective reality,’ the terrain of ‘superstructures’” (2014: 118). This dividing line between ideology as consciousness and ideology as superstructure will be crucial for the discussion that follows, but for now I want merely to emphasize the commonality between the two: conflict. The Leninist approach to ideology read Marx’s line from 1859 as an injunction to become conscious of the revolutionary struggle underway and to fight it out in ideological struggle.

    Lenin’s argument in What Is to Be Done? is nearly the opposite of the standard picture. Rather than concerning himself with how to shape and direct an inert mass of workers, or with “the danger of spontaneity” among the workers (Scott 2008: 155), Lenin’s concern is that the “spontaneous” or elementary aspects of working class resistance are vulnerable, both to the power of bosses and landlords, and to outside meddling by the bourgeois and tsarist press and other agents of influence.[27] When workers begin to agitate for improvements in wages, working conditions, and treatment on the job, their efforts attract the attention and speech of those who want to lead them “‘along the line of least resistance,’” into a form of trade unionism that believed that “adding a kopeck to the rouble is nearer and more to be valued than any socialism or any politics” (in Lih 2008: 711, 707). Elementary organizing is also vulnerable to “the Zubatovs of the world who drag it along the line of a priest/gendarme ‘ideology’” (in Lih 2008: 711).[28]

    In the face of this vulnerability, Lenin thought it irresponsible of socialists to wring their hands over the fact that they may not be workers themselves or to think that they should not themselves “interfere” in the process of class formation and struggle. Lenin dubbed this passive attitude on the part of socialists – the belief that a commitment to working class self-emancipation implied leaving the workers alone to find their own path to freedom, or, at most, aiding them in their local, economic struggles – “bowing to spontaneity.” His point was that leaving the workers alone to find their own way to freedom was also leaving them at the mercy of their more powerful oppressors. The duty of solidarity with the oppressed implies also a duty to do everything you can to figure out and help to implement a political strategy that can actually lead to their self-emancipation. A hands-off approach on the part of socialists, after all, would not imply that the monarchists, reactionaries, and bourgeois liberals would also take a hands-off approach. It would mean “leav[ing] the field of activity” to the opponents of emancipation (in Lih 2008: 711).

    This leads Lenin to make some of his most controversial claims. Quoting Karl Kautsky, the recognized dean of the SPD, the most important social-democratic mass party in the world, Lenin affirmed:

    Modern socialist awareness can emerge only on the basis of profound scientific knowledge. In fact, modern economic science is as much a condition of socialist production as modern, say, technology. The proletariat, even if it wanted to, cannot create either the one or the other: both emerge from the modern social process. The carrier of science is not the proletariat, but the bourgeois intelligentsia (Kautsky’s emphasis): modern socialism emerges in the heads of individual members of this stratum and then is communicated by them to proletarians who stand out due to their mental development, who in turn bring it into the class struggle of the proletariat where conditions allow. In this way, socialist awareness is something brought in to the class struggle of the proletariat from without, and not something that emerges from the class struggle in elemental fashion.[29]

    Lenin clarifies in a footnote:

    This does not mean, of course, that workers do not participate in this working­ out [of a socialist awareness]. But they participate not qua workers, but qua theoreticians of socialism – as Proudhons and Weitlings. In other words, they participate only insofar as they succeed to a greater or lesser extent in attaining a command of the knowledge of their century and in advancing that knowledge. In order for workers to succeed in doing this more often, it is necessary to occupy ourselves as much as possible in raising the level of purposiveness of workers in general – it is necessary for workers not to confine themselves within the narrow framework of ‘writing for workers’ but to study to achieve a greater and greater command of what is written for all. Instead of saying ‘confine themselves,’ we should really say ‘are confined’ – because the workers themselves read and want to read all that is written for the intelligentsia, and only some (bad) intellectuals think that it is sufficient ‘for the workers’ to talk about factory conditions and chew over what has long been known. (In Lih 2008: 710)

    Unfortunately, professors of political science don’t read the footnotes, it seems, since Scott takes Lenin to be saying that socialism is an alien doctrine that must be instilled into workers otherwise innocent of it, whose “own history and values … will lead the working class in the wrong direction unless they are replaced” (2008: 150). Instead, Lenin is arguing something more prosaic and reasonable: that working fifty or sixty hours a week in terrible conditions for starvation wages, while it gives you many grievances and reasons to protest, does not allow you much time or wherewithal to figure out how the world might be recast so that you don’t have to – that no one has to – be trapped in that position any longer.

    Nonetheless, it is this prosaic and reasonable argument that contains all of the elements of the false consciousness thesis. Lenin believes that the workers’ vital interests are at stake in the fight for socialism, that socialism will mean freedom and dignity and plenty, and that “the entire present-day social system” – not only but especially in Russia – “is built on looting and oppression” (in Lih 2008: 724). He also believes that only the working classes themselves – the proletariat in alliance with the peasantry – can end this looting and oppression, first, by aiding the bourgeoisie and the liberal nobility in overthrowing the tsarist autocracy, and then, in a second step, by taking the entire political administration, and all of the estates and factories, into their own hands. But this course of action requires a massive concerted effort, on a national scale – indeed, an international scale – for a goal that may take decades to realize, and against the opposition of an entrenched and powerful enemy with command over the army, navy, and police apparatus.

    In other words, although the achievement of socialism would, according to Lenin, serve the interests of the vast majority, the fight for socialism would also imperil and harm the interests of many workers. To fight against the tsar and for socialism, workers must risk their jobs, their homes, their lives, and their families – everything tangible and near at hand – for the sake of something uncertain, abstract, and far away.

    This conflict of interests between the emancipatory interests of the oppressed and their immediate material interests, or between their reasons for getting free and their reasons for getting by, is what makes ideological struggle – theory, propaganda, agitation, organizing – so critically important.

    This is why Lenin thinks an all-Russian political newspaper is what is to be done. Only by connecting local and minor indignities and affronts, such as “factory abuses, … police violence [or] the government’s actions that are so biased toward the capitalists,” to “the area of the relations of all classes and [social] strata to the state and to the government – the area of the interrelations between all classes,” can the social democrats make the case that the emancipatory interests ought to win out (in Lih 2008: 745–46). Only a national political paper, Lenin thought, could aspire to be “a people’s tribune,” which “can respond to each and every manifestation of abuse of power and oppression, wherever it occurs, whatever stratum or class it concerns, [which] can generalise all these manifestations into one big picture of police violence and capitalist exploitation, [which] is able to use each small affair to set before everybody his socialist convictions and his democratic demands and to explain to each and all the world-historical significance of the liberation struggle of the proletariat.”

    This project of agitating and organizing among an oppressed group, on behalf of their interest in emancipation, posits, of necessity, a distinction between the commitment to that emancipatory interest and commitment to other, more immediate and local interests. Lenin, following SPD usage, called the former – the goal of socialist agitation and organizing – “social democratic consciousness,” but also “class political consciousness” or “class political awareness.” Kautsky had referred to this as the proletariat’s “awareness of its position and … awareness of its task” (Lih 2008: 710). It descends to us, for the most part, as class consciousness.

    It fell to György Lukács to formulate the opposition between class consciousness and false consciousness, but the name matters less than the thing itself. False consciousness is just the difference between your interests as you actually perceive them – your empirically experienced desires and goals – and the emancipatory interests of the class to which you belong, or the distance between what you want and what would be rational from the perspective of the collective self-emancipation of those in your social position. As we have seen, Lenin associates this distance, in the case of the Russian workers, with the extent to which “the ideological enslavement of the workers by the bourgeoisie” has gone unchallenged by the activity of committed socialists (in Lih 2008: 711). Thus, false consciousness is equivalent to ideological subjection, or to serving the interests of your oppressors rather than the emancipatory interests of your own class.

    This formulation has a reasonable core – an indispensable core, even – but is susceptible to two significant dangers. It is not only reasonable but unavoidable that activists for self-emancipation will both differentiate the emancipatory interest of the dominated from their other interests and urge the dominated to subordinate their quotidian and worldly  interests to their interest in being free. Being dominated, after all, gives the dominated good reasons to comply, to go along, to keep their heads down, and to cooperate with their dominators. To engage in a collective struggle for self-emancipation requires discounting those reasons. It requires elevating the interest in freedom to the premier position, and this means also elevating the cause of the dominated group as a whole over your personal desires and goals. It also necessitates increasing the social costs of compliance and cooperation with the dominant. The vocabulary developed for those who prioritize the goods that can be obtained from the dominant over the common emancipatory interest of the dominated provides a vantage point for spying this process: toady, creeper, sycophant, bootlicker, flunkey, stooge, brown-noser, scab, tool, dupe. These are, in effect, the vernacular names for those subject, in Ecclesiastical Latin, to “false consciousness” or “ideological subjection.”

    The two dangers lurking in Lenin’s formulation of this elementary point are closely related. As dangers, they are probably inherent in the problem of self-emancipation, but Lenin’s formulation amplifies them in a particular way. The first danger is that of forgetting that our interest in freedom is itself instrumental. Freedom from domination is a basic good for human beings because domination is a burden on our other desires and plans. Hence, subordinating our quotidian interests to our interest in freedom can only ever make sense as an exception. The whole reason we ought to want to be free is because freedom would allow us to get on with living our lives as we think is best, without having to navigate the extraneous motivations generated by the power of the dominant. Freedom is not the end of human life, human life is the end of freedom. Thinking the opposite inflates our interest in freedom into something coextensive with or even constitutive of our humanity itself. It thereby inflates our interest in freedom into the moral demand to see the world from the purely human standpoint of “the world-historical consciousness, the awakening of humanity to self-consciousness,” and the struggle against domination into “a means by which humanity liberates itself” (Lukács 1972: 6).

    The second danger is not found in the concept of false consciousness itself but in something that easily goes unexamined in its counterpart, class consciousness in its political, paradigmatically socialist form. False consciousness is a many-splendored thing, full of variation and detail. There are a million ways to fall away from “the narrow, steep path of correct action,” a million “gesture[s] of solidarity with the existing order” (Lukács 1972: 6). Since the domination against which people fight defines the contours of social space, moving through that space in any direction means following those contours, and the compromises with the dominant can be catalogued endlessly. There is a corresponding tendency to represent socialist or class consciousness as if it were one definite thing, a pinpoint opposed to this manifold of compromises and complicities.

    Hence, Lenin claims that “any disparagement of socialist ideology, any distancing from it signals in and of itself a strengthening of bourgeois ideology,” as if socialist ideology were one thing with obvious boundaries and a clear location, from which any distance could be observed and measured (in Lih 2008: 710). Likewise, Lukács’s “narrow, steep path of correct action” is “prescribed by the philosophy of history which alone leads to the goal,” as if this could be discerned (1972: 6). To be sure, Lukács realizes that, “by the very nature of the matter, we can only talk in terms of a possibility” of realizing emancipation by our actions, but he clearly thinks of this possibility only in terms of whether or not a policy will end up succeeding at a particular juncture, not whether or not it is the right policy. Otherwise, it would make no sense for him to claim that, “for the individual who seizes this possibility” there can be “no choice and no hesitation” – “if,” that is, “he is a socialist” (1972: 10). What it is to be a socialist is treated as if it were self-clarifying, and as if those committed to self-emancipation faced no real burdens of judgment, but only burdens of conscience.

    To an important extent, both of these dangers are simply the occupational hazards of activists and organizers. Those who have subjectively committed themselves to the cause of emancipation – who have dedicated their lives and subordinated all their other interests to the emancipatory interest – are as inclined to self-justification as anyone else. They are also inclined to magnify the stakes of disagreements with one another. When these two inclinations reinforce one another and are not checked by anything else, the result is something like Lukács’s conviction that “the Communist Party must be the primary incarnation of the realm of freedom; [that] above all, the spirit of comradeliness, of true solidarity, and of self-sacrifice must govern everything it does” (1972: 69). Here, self-sacrifice is identified with freedom itself, and the subjective commitment of the revolutionary is transformed into the aim of the revolution – as if the aim of revolution were to make revolutionaries rather than to make revolutionaries unnecessary. This is a perverse betrayal of the entire project of self-emancipation, since it turns our interest in being free into a self-refuting interest in being without interests.

    It is also a return to La Boétie’s three principles of subjection. First, the sphere of the economy is reconceived as a second nature, leading people to act in mystified ways at odds with true humanity and true rationality. Second, consent is manufactured by the ruling class (and by the alienation of the proletariat’s own activity) through the manipulation of incentives and ideologies. Finally, opportunism is an ever-present danger to the revolutionary party, since everyone is susceptible to being tempted by immediate and personal gains. And, just as in La Boétie, “where the danger lies, also grows the saving power.” The elitism of the Leninist tradition is not rooted in any disdain for the spontaneous self-activity of the masses, but rather in its exclusive attention to the actions and inclinations of the politically conscious few, who can decide the fate of a class by either their steadfastness or their opportunism. It may well be necessary to inflate the importance of the spirit of comradeliness, solidarity, and self-sacrifice, precisely in order to impress upon the revolutionary activists a sense of honor and commitment, a new form of the ancient voluntary servitude, by which promising young people devote themselves to the party and the cause. This strategic gambit, however, risks undermining the robustness of Marxist social theory by inflating the importance and efficacy of voluntary action and ideological commitment. It may even endanger the very idea of self-emancipation by casting revolutionaries as heroic founders and guardians of the people.

    Nonetheless, it is a significant overreaction to these dangers to conclude, as Michael Rosen does, that “it follows from the theory of ideology that the working class’s own perception of what would further its interests is distorted and inadequate.” Distinguishing “between what people actually believe and what they ought to believe” regarding their interests is simply unavoidable, even for liberals like Destutt de Tracy and Gaus. It is not dependent upon the concept of ideology as false consciousness, nor is it any special inducement towards “acting on behalf of” people rather than as their “representative” (Rosen 1996: 271–72). The false consciousness thesis is, moreover, a reasonable application of the distinction between desires and interests to a context of domination. The dangers lie further downstream.

     

    6. False consciousness and class consciousness

    It was Lukács, more than anyone, who turned Lenin’s political practice of ideological struggle into a theory of false consciousness, and it was the Frankfurt School, primarily, that turned Lukács’s theory, which pertained to exactly one class, into a generic theoretical practice of ideology critique. Both of these operations involved highly-complex series of arguments and were embedded in discursive contexts that are hard to reconstruct. Therefore, what follows falls far short of a demonstration of the claims I am advancing. In particular, there are two reasonable concerns that must be acknowledged. First, Lukács’s History and Class Consciousness was only posthumously inducted into the Ideologiekritik hall of fame. “Ideology” is not a central term in the book, and neither “reification” nor “class consciousness” can be reduced to ideology. Second, the Frankfurt School tradition of critical theory was also much broader and more heterogeneous and experimental than a focus on Ideologiekritik might suggest. However, neither of these concerns need deter us. The question guiding this essay is how theories of ideology have emerged from and might inform the project of self-emancipation, and this question is a cleaver not a scalpel: it cuts through this history to reveal a facet, rather than entering into it to access its inner anatomy. It is because Lukács sought to theorize Lenin’s practice that his writings from 1919-23 produce a theory of ideological false consciousness, and it is because the Frankfurt School sought to reconsider self-emancipation from the ground up that they produced a practice of ideology critique. An outline of this trajectory emerges from a few reference points.

    The final months and aftermath of World War I saw numerous socialist and communist revolutions in eastern and central Europe, all of which collapsed or were defeated. The Finnish Civil War ended with the defeat of the Reds on April 1918. The November Revolution in Germany gave rise to the short-lived council republics in Bavaria, Bremen, and Saxony, and to the abortive Spartacist uprising in Berlin.[30] By August 1919, however, all of these were decisively put down; uprisings and rebellions would continue through 1923, but these were increasingly pale imitations of the events of 1918-19, and the Weimar Republic, while it remained shaky, was never in real danger from the Left. The Hungarian council republic, with Lukács as education commissioner, lasted one hundred thirty-three days in the middle of 1919. Its Slovakian adjunct lasted only three weeks. The workers’ councils of Italy’s Biennio Rosso were disowned by the Italian Socialist Party and the socialist union, the CGL, and so the only attempt at a council republic, the month-long Labin Republic, came in response to fascist attacks in Istria in 1921.

    The Communist Party of Hungary was founded by Béla Kun and others in October 1918. Lukács joined in November. By February 1919, he was a member of the central committee. By June he was the education commissioner in Kun’s government, leading the nationalization of private schools, the extension of general education, and the revision of university curriculum. After the collapse of the Hungarian Red Army, which was divided between nationalist and communist aspirations, Lukács helped organize the underground party before fleeing to Austria. He narrowly avoided extradition to Horthy’s regime, and the following period of exile saw his most influential theoretical writings.

    It is commonplace to say that the failures of the period – from the SPD’s support of the war through the inability of communists to expand the revolution to the consolidation of an anti-Soviet European bloc – animate Lukács’s theory of 1919-23. This is too easy, though, since the writing of Tactics and Ethics are impelled more by the Bolshevik success of 1917 than by anything else, and there is no theoretical break between these militant texts and those of History and Class Consciousness. Success and failure alike animate these writings in the direction of, in Lukács’s own later, self-critical words, “a messianic sectarianism” that proposes “the most radical methods” of resolving every issue (1971: xii). “The greatest tragedy of the workers’ movement,” wrote Lukács in 1920, “has always been its inability to tear itself completely free from the ideological matrix of capitalism” (1972: 67).[31] This diagnosis presupposes, however, the thesis that it also reinforces, that only “a total break with every institution and mode of life stemming from the bourgeois world” could “foster an undistorted class consciousness in the vanguard, in the Communist parties and in the Communist youth organizations” (Lukács 1971: xiv).

    This total break with the bourgeois world can only arise imminently. Indeed, it can only arise from the very center of the bourgeois world itself: the factory where commodities are used to make commodities. According to Lukács, “capitalist society in its totality” can only be understood on the basis of “the structure of commodity-relations” (1971: 83). This structure is revealed by Marx in the fetishism section near the beginning of Capital, and its “essence” is “that a relation between people takes on the character of a thing and thus acquires a ‘phantom objectivity,’ an autonomy that seems so strictly rational and all-embracing as to conceal every trace” of its basis in human interrelations (1971: 83). Capitalist society is commodified through-and-through, according to Lukács, such that “every expression of life” is permeated by this fetish character (1971: 84). “The personal nature of economic relations” is hidden away by the “non-human objectivity of the natural laws of society, and humanity is locked in “servitude to the ‘second nature’ so created” (1971: 86–87).

    At the heart of this “reified” society stands the factory where commodities are made. Its “internal organization” contains, Lukács believes, “the whole structure of capitalist society” in miniature (1971: 90). Lukács has two stories about why this is so, neither very convincing. First, à la Adam Smith,[32] if every social relation abroad in capitalist society is structured by the commodity – rationalized, economized, subject to cost-benefit analysis – then this is nowhere more true and more observable than in the factory.[33] The factory is, as it were, the “concentrated form” of society, in which its essential, structuring processes are visible to the eye and palpable in their intensity (Lukács 1971: 90). Lukács’s second story is a causal one. If every social relation abroad in capitalist society is structured by commodities, and commodities are created in a capitalist factory, then, by transitivity, every social relation can be said to originate in the capitalist factory. “The fate of the worker becomes the fate of society as a whole,” since the process by which the worker’s “own labor becomes something objective and independent of him, something that controls him by virtue of an autonomy alien to man,” is also the process by which “a world of objects and relations between things springs into being” (1971: 91, 87).

    This causal story is the more important one for Lukács, since it contains, he thinks, the key to the possibility that the working class could “break with every institution and mode of life stemming from the bourgeois world.” Since the workers of that world, by making the commodities of that world, in fact make also all of the social relations of that world, the working class has a unique “ability to see society from the center, as a coherent whole” (Lukács 1971: 69). The proletariat, considered collectively, possesses a virtual maker’s knowledge of the whole bourgeois world. Everything stems from their activity and, so, if they can find new ways of relating to one another, sharing their knowledge and powers directly with one another, they could remake the world entirely. Moreover, since they make the whole world as commodified labor-power, Lukács thinks they have a privileged access to the commodity structure itself. As commodities that make commodities, the proletariat is, in Lukács’s famous phrase, “able to discover within itself on the basis of its life-experience the identical subject-object” (1971: 149). That is, “the self-understanding of the proletariat” is supposed, by Lukács, to be “simultaneously the objective understanding of the nature of society” (1971: 149).

    This, the standpoint of the proletariat, is not any sort of empirical description of what workers know or think or want. Lukács’s analysis is supposed to point towards “the objective theory of class consciousness,” which is only “the theory of its objective possibility” (1971: 79).[34] The problem, as always, is “whether it is actually possible to make the objective possibility of class consciousness into a reality,” and this “ideological crisis” is the highest priority for communist militants” (1971: 79). The situation of the individual proletarian – or individual group of proletarians – exerts selective pressure to prioritize achievable local goals, such as better pay and better job security, over long-term and high-risk strategies like mobilizing for revolution.

    Lukács knows this. He highlights it. He locates “in the center of proletarian class consciousness … an antagonism [Widerspruch] between momentary interest and ultimate goal” (1971: 73). But this just leads him to double down: “class consciousness is identical with neither the psychological consciousness of individual members of the proletariat, nor with the (mass-psychological) consciousness of the proletariat as a whole; but it is, on the contrary, the sense, become conscious, of the historical role of the class” (1971: 73). In other words, the rationally appropriate strategy for anyone located in the class position of the proletariat is to recognize the long-term untenability of reforms to capitalism and to embrace revolutionary socialism.

    This is too convenient by half. It simply presupposes that the proletariat makes the whole world, and will make the whole world consciously just to the extent that individual proletarians become psychologically conscious of belonging to the class that makes the whole world. Lukács’s construction of class consciousness reduces, therefore, to a pure morality, in the sense Hegel gives to Moralität – a proper self-relation or conscience – that is supposed to guarantee right action. This recapitulates a major theme of Tactics and Ethics, where Lukács explicitly criticizes Hegel for letting “the system of material, spiritual and social goods” – the sphere of ethical substance and objective right – displace and subsume “the most primitive, universal psychological facts: conscience and the sense of responsibility” (1972: 7). “Hegel’s system is devoid of ethics,” and this is one of “the dangerous aspects of the Hegelian legacy in Marxism,” a danger against which only class consciousness can preserve it (1972: 6–7).

    Imputed proletarian class consciousness is simply the rational-moral capacity recreate the totality of human society, the “higher power” which must replace “the blind power of economic forces” and which “corresponds more exactly to the dignity of man” (Lukács 1972: 5). Marxism, as a method, provides “the knowledge of the whole and of the whole as a process,” or knowledge of “the totality of human society” and of “what the development of this totality means for the proletariat in terms of tasks” (1972: 93–94). However, this “penetration of all fields of knowledge” is, at present, “still only a demand posed to science: a demand which can be fulfilled only in and through the revolution” (1972: 94). As they become psychologically conscious of their power, workers form “revolutionary workers’ councils,” which embody “the economic and political defeat of reification,” since they tend to abolish all separations: “the bourgeois separation of the legislature, administration, and judiciary,” as well as “the fragmentation of the proletariat in time and space” and the separation between “economics and politics” (Lukács 1971: 80). In short, the real proletarians, as soon as they are really conscious of being proletarian, will act in a really proletarian manner to consciously and methodically create the totality of society as a unity – and thereby also to cancel their existence as proletarians by eliminating classes altogether.

    This is perfect example of what Hegel criticized in Moralität. It posits a form of consciousness that sees all, knows all, and acts only and always for the sake of humanity as a whole, and claims that the effectiveness of this consciousness “can only come about as the product of the – free – action of the proletariat itself” (Lukács 1971: 29). That the proletariat is capable of the conscious and unified creation of the social totality – the total conscious production of society – is simply a matter to be taken on faith. Any failure to rationally produce this self-conscious society is a failure to achieve the self-canceling proletarian class consciousness. To ask how this consciousness proceeds to determine its acts is to admit that one does not possess this consciousness.

    Lukács presumes that Marx’s theoretical critique of political economy also has the effect of making transparent to the proletariat their demiurge-like position at the center of society. In proletarian class consciousness, conscious self-justification and self-understanding catches its own tail and turns thereby into a prospective knowledge of how to transform society in accordance with human intentions. The owl of Minerva is reborn as the eagle of Zeus, all-seeing and provident. A new ideology is born – communist ideology – but one with a distinct advantage over Destutt de Tracy’s bourgeois ideology: it can actually grasp the totality of social relations and thereby transform social relations at will. Like Destutt de Tracy’s ideology, Lukács’s ideology issues in a pedagogy, but it aims at an education in “the moral mission” and “spiritual leadership” of the Communist Party (Lukács 1972: 12–17, 49–52, 64–70). Without doing away with opportunism in fact, communist morality provides assurances that opportunism is becoming irrelevant. Every other proletarian is situated just as we are, and every other proletarian’s real needs are also expressed in communist morality. So long as we have faith that the party embodies the “consciousness of the realm of freedom” (Lukács 1971: 54), we have evidence of what we cannot see. Class consciousness undergirds or guarantees that “the infinitely painful path of the proletarian revolution, with its many reverses, its constant return to its starting point,” nonetheless “leads out of the impasses of capitalism,” by making the contradiction between necessity and freedom irrelevant for practical purposes (Lukács 1972: 68).

    On Lukács’s understanding, communist society can only exist if, rather than mistaking “the actual psychological state of consciousness of proletarians for the class consciousness of the proletariat,” we “regard the particular interest and the struggle to achieve it as a means of education for the final battle whose outcome depends on closing the gap between the psychological consciousness and the imputed one” (1971: 74). Communist morality is an attempt to “educate the whole of humanity in freedom and self-discipline,” but also, crucially, to educate “its members from the very beginning,” and to do so by “purging the party … based on ‘a constant stepping-up of demands in relation to real communist achievements’” (Lukács 1972: 68).[35] Each of these activities encourages and depends upon the others, and the logical structure that emerges is, like all triangular constructions, very stable and robust. Communist morality seeks to overcome voluntary servitude – ideological subjection – by going all in.

     

    7. Ideology critique as ideology

    Mid-twentieth-century social theory took Lukács’s hypothesis seriously, but also took a generic humanism seriously enough to generalize the hypothesis to all human agents. What was in Lukács’s hands a partisan ideology of communist militancy became an omni-historical fact of human life: the social construction of reality.[36] When this is operationalized, however, it becomes immediately apparent that, rather than the transparency and conscious control promised by Lukács, the result is an ever-renewed and massive opacity of social institutions. Made by “us” and re-makeable by “us,” they constantly confront us as made by others and resistant to any change we can initiate. With the generalization of ideology, “the level of the sociology of knowledge is reached – the understanding that no human thought … is immune to the ideologizing influences of its social context” (Berger and Luckmann 1990: 9). The social world becomes the world of meaning, and ideological division becomes the interminable contest between different meanings of the world.

    This move did not require doing any great violence to Lukács’s argument.[37] The standpoint of the proletariat, after all, was found not in the heads of factory operatives and farm hands but in Marx’s Capital. “Among Hegelian Marxists like Lukács,” Habermas rightly noted, there was no strong commitment to the determination of consciousness by economic practice, or even to the weaker thesis that economic life places limits on the possibilities for cultural or intellectual life. Rather, “the concept of the social totality excludes a model of levels,” such as Marx and Engels’s model of base and superstructure. Instead of levels, base and superstructure are interpreted as essence and appearance, with the economic structure “being conceived dialectically as the essence that comes to existence in the observable appearances” (1979: 143). Thus, Lukács’s theory of ideology could be “assimilated in the form of the Sociology of Knowledge” without social theorists having to bother themselves with the analysis of production, exploitation, and exchange (Habermas 1973: 204).

    The significant result of Lukács’s reconstruction of Marx and Lenin, along this line of reception, is simply that, in Horkheimer’s formulation, “​​the world which is given to the individual and which he must accept and take into account is, in its present and continuing form, a product of the activity of society as a whole” (1982: 200). For the critical theory of Horkheimer and his colleagues, what differentiates the working class is not necessarily that they have a special role in producing the social world, but that they are on the receiving end of a social world “in which the extreme development of technology has made the masses in principle superfluous as producers in their own country” (Horkheimer and Adorno 2002: 121). According to Horkheimer and Adorno,

    The gradations in the standard of living correspond very precisely to the degree by which classes and individuals inwardly adhere to the system. Managers can be relied on; even the minor employee Dagwood, who lives in reality no less than in the comic strip, is reliable. But anyone who goes hungry and suffers from cold, especially if he once had good prospects, is a marked man. He is an outsider, and – with the occasional exception of the capital crime – to be an outsider is the gravest guilt. (2002: 120–21)

    The poor, the oppressed, the excluded, and the critical are all in a similar situation. They cannot accept that the way things are is the way things have to be, or the best that they can be.

    And yet the poor, the oppressed, and the excluded do accept it, practically speaking, since they do not, by and large, work to transform society. The critical theorist situates herself in this gap between the acceptable and the accepted and, rather than asking how “one or another abuse” can be eliminated, takes as her guideline the intuition that all such abuses are “necessarily connected with the way in which the social structure is organized” as a whole (Horkheimer 1982: 207). This intuition is given a recognizably Leninist formulation by Horkheimer and Adorno:

    Although the abundance of goods which could be produced everywhere and simultaneously makes the struggle for raw materials and markets seem ever more anachronistic, humanity is nevertheless divided into a small number of armed power blocs. They compete more pitilessly than the firms involved in the anarchy of commodity production ever did, and strive toward mutual liquidation. The more senseless the antagonism, the more rigid the blocs. Only the total identification of the population with these monstrosities of power, so deeply imprinted as to have become second nature and stopping all the pores of consciousness, maintains the masses in the state of absolute apathy which makes them capable of their miraculous achievements. As far as any decisions are still left to individuals, they are effectively decided in advance. (2002: 169)

    Horkheimer fleshes out this “second nature,” which maintains apathy by “stopping all the pores of consciousness,” in the following terms:

    The individual as a rule must simply accept the basic conditions of his existence as given and strive to fulfill them; he finds his satisfaction and praise in accomplishing as well as he can the tasks connected with his place in society and in courageously doing his duty despite all the sharp criticism he may choose to exercise in particular matters. … The separation between individual and society in virtue of which the individual accepts as natural the limits prescribed for his activity is relativized in critical theory. The latter considers the overall framework which is conditioned by the blind interaction of individual activities (that is, the existent division of labor and the class distinctions) to be a function which originates in human action and therefore is a possible object of planful decision and rational determination of goals. (1982: 207)

    The Frankfurt School generally follows this line of argument. What Lukács referred to as “the knowledge that social facts are not objects but relations between men” becomes, for the critical theorist, the knowledge that all social facts are norms. The realm of society is coextensive with the space of reasons. If social facts are norms, that means they exist for a reason, they serve some human purpose. The question becomes: do they exist as they are for good reasons, and are those reasons accessible and acceptable to all?

    The legacy of ideology theory entails, however, that people’s presently expressed opinions and preferences are not dispositive. Although “the idea of a reasonable organization of society that will meet the needs of the whole community” is, according to Horkheimer, “immanent in human work” as such, this idea is not “correctly grasped by individuals or by the common mind,” and Marx and Engels were wrong to think that the special situation and interests of the proletariat would be a “guarantee of correct knowledge” of this idea (1982: 213). The proletariat is divided by the social structure itself, and their local perspectives and interests mean that, even for them, “the world superficially seems quite different than it really is” (Horkheimer 1982: 214).

    Therefore, if critical theorists cannot simply ask people – including oppressed people – if social norms are rationally acceptable to them, then they need a theory that can play the role Capital played for Lukács: a theoretical exposition of the objective possibility of class consciousness, on the basis of which they can attempt “​​to hasten developments which will lead to a society without injustice” (Horkheimer 1982: 221). This hastening is equated by Horkheimer with the critical theorist’s task of “reduc[ing] the tension between his own insight and oppressed humanity in whose service he thinks” (1982: 221). The theory in question, then, must indicate how it is possible for the everyday consciousness of the oppressed and the enlightened consciousness of the critical theorist to be united. This objective theory of the possible unity of everyday and enlightened consciousness is developed most fully and most explicitly in Habermas’s account of communicative rationality.

    Raymond Geuss has reconstructed the linkages between the early articulations of critical theory in the work of Horkheimer, Adorno, and Marcuse, and the development it underwent in the hands of Habermas.[38] As Geuss demonstrates, the central strand of continuity is a shared normative conception of power. For the Frankfurt School, Herrschaft is essentially voluntary in the Boétian sense. “‘Herrschaft,’” Geuss writes, “is power to exercise normative repression,” where “normative repression” is the “frustration of agents’ preferences which makes a claim to legitimacy that is accepted by those agents because of certain normative beliefs they hold” (1981: 16).

    The dominated, on this account, consent to their domination, by definition.[39] More than this, they think their domination is right or good in some sense. As Geuss puts it, “repression is ‘normative’ if the agents are prevented from pursuing their interests by a set of normative beliefs they accept,” and Herrschaft is just the asymmetrical power of normative repression (1981: 34–35; emphasis added). The normative beliefs of the dominated, therefore, are the source of their frustration or repression. The claim of legitimacy, in other words, is not just a claim made by the dominant, but is accepted by the dominated.

    This does not necessarily mean that the legitimacy belief is the basic normative belief, however. The dominated may consent to their domination and believe it to be good because it seems to them the most reasonable means of realizing an independently held normative belief. They may believe that God’s will should be done, and that mortal flesh is weak, and that this weakness requires, therefore, a firm government by a divinely ordained minister, and that the royal line of the Hohenzollerns happens to provide this needed government here and now. The legitimacy of Carol I is not basic to their moral worldview, and their joyous consent to his rule – and the consequent frustration of their pursuit of their own interests – is not entirely personalistic, but depends upon more fundamental moral beliefs, together with some basic factual judgments about the royal succession, etc.

    Nonetheless, this is a very strong version of the voluntary servitude thesis. The normative beliefs of the dominated are the fundamental cause of the repression they experience. The dominated suffer from “false consciousness” and from unfreedom, but “the ‘unfree existence’” from which they suffer “is a form of self-imposed coercion,” since its “‘power’ or ‘objectivity’ derives only from the fact that the agents do not realize that it is self-imposed” (Geuss 1981: 58).

    This last claim, that the objectivity of their unfreedom is self-imposed, must be expanded upon. Not only is ideological false consciousness the primary cause of the repression experienced by the dominated, it also gives rise to “real social oppression” that is “objective,” in the sense that a group of rational agents would arrive at a consensus judgment that it exists – i.e., it is not imaginary or ‘in the heads’ of the oppressed (Geuss 1981: 74, 72). In Habermas’s later formulation, the subsystems of the economy and the state “congeal into the ‘second nature’ of norm-free sociality that can appear as something in the objective world, as an objectified context of life” (1987: 183). The “objective power” of this second nature cannot be “automatically resolved by critical reflection” (Geuss 1981: 74). The dominant have an interest in the maintenance of the oppressive status quo, and “established social institutions” are not undone simply by people losing faith in their legitimacy (1981: 75).

    However, the Frankfurt School – at least from the second generation on – is nonetheless committed to the notion that the objectivity of these social institutions and the conservative interests rooted in them are consequences of self-imposed ideological coercion. Even if “enlightenment does not automatically bring emancipation in the sense of freedom from the external coercion exercised by social institutions,” enlightenment is a prerequisite of freedom from external coercion because external coercion is the house that false consciousness built (Geuss 1981: 75). False consciousness has motivated the construction of an objective, institutional world, and this second nature will not be torn down by critical theory alone, but critical theory is a prerequisite to that tearing down, just as false consciousness was a prerequisite for the building.[40] Consciousness comes first, as a motive for action, in both cases.[41]

    According to Geuss, the epistemic element of ideology critique is inseparable from – indeed, is fully constituted by – the normative element. Although “Ideologiekritik is not just a form of ‘moralizing criticism,’” – although it criticizes ideology for being false, and is, therefore, itself “a cognitive enterprise, a form of knowledge”(1981: 26) – this cognitive element of ideology critique turns out to be the articulation of the “optimal conditions” of “perfect knowledge and freedom” in which we could formulate our “true interests,” or the set of desires that “could be rationally integrated into a coherent ‘good life’” (1981: 48). Forst, who eschews any reference to “true interests,” grounds ideology critique in “a right to justification of social and political relations” that rules out any norms that “justify a social situation of asymmetry and subordination with bad reasons that could not be shared among free and equal justificatory agents in a practice of justification free from such asymmetry and distortion” (2015: 117). In either case, false consciousness is false because it comprises normative views about how we should live that we could not arrive at in a condition of perfect knowledge and freedom, and that we therefore cannot reflectively endorse here and now.[42]

    Therefore, the Frankfurt School reasserts the critique of ideology, but not by pointing to the reality of social dynamics that frustrate our efforts at conscious control and that falsify our normative ideals. Instead, ideology critique is the critique of every value, every meaning, by reference to a posited counterfactual ideal speech situation. Habermas would not describe this situation as Horkheimer did: “a state of affairs in which there will be no exploitation or oppression, in which an all-embracing subject, namely self-aware mankind, exists, and in which it is possible to speak of a unified theoretical creation and a thinking that transcends individuals” (1982: 241). Nonetheless, the discourse theoretical invocation of “the procedures and presuppositions under which justifications can have the power to produce consensus” retains the same basic contours (Habermas 1979: 205). Our allegiance to this world – that is, this world’s empirical legitimacy – is undermined by the rational projection of another world, a world free of coercion, asymmetry, and temporal restraints, where rational conversation would be the only determinant of meaning and value.

    The entire Marxian problematic has here been stood on its head. Marx and Engels’s criticism of “the German ideology” was that, like the French original, it sought to transform society by changing people’s minds so as to realize ideals that had been abstracted from the very social practices that frustrated those ideals. This project is, according to Marx and Engels, superstructure idealism or protagonism. By the time ideology critique arrives in Frankfurt, whatever frustrates our efforts at conscious control or falsifies our normative ideals is identified as itself ideological, or as the reified second nature that ideological justifications “eventually materialize into” (Forst 2015: 124). At the same time, the nonexistent society of voluntary and mutually-beneficial relations, together with the effort, here-and-now, to realize that world by means of the unforced force of the stronger argument is non-ideological. Ideology critique has taken the place of ideology, and collective self-emancipation has been whittled down to intersubjective self-enlightenment.

     

    8. Ideology without false consciousness

    Lenin’s practice of ideological struggle also received a second theoretical articulation, however, quite distinct from Lukács’s, in Antonio Gramsci’s Quaderni del carcere. This articulation is no less Hegelian than Lukács’s, but it resonates more with the Sittlichkeit or ethical life of Elements of the Philosophy of Right than with either its Moralität or the absolute knowing of the Phenomenology. It concerns itself with habits, institutions, and cultivation, rather than with consciousness, rationality, and validity claims.

    The specificity of Gramsci’s approach stands out starkly in what would have been the first discussion of ideology that a francophone or anglophone reader of the Quaderni encountered: the discussion of Croce’s conception of ideology and politics in a note entitled “Politics as an autonomous science.”[43] Croce – akin to Lukács – associates ideology, including politics, with error, and traces error back to its origin in “passion,” understood in a Hegelian-dialectical sense as “the non-definitive character … of the term of the dialectic which the latter must transcend in its forward movement” (Gramsci 1971: 138). Gramsci counters that “Croce’s conception of politics/passion excludes parties, since it is not possible to think of an organized and permanent passion”; if there are permanent political passions, then they are not passions at all, but “rationality and deliberate reflection” (1971: 138–39). Gramsci aligns these terms with Marx’s base/superstructure model – as did Croce – in order to assert that what is passing and perishable, or what is merely the “apparent” surface of the social structure, is also necessary to that structure, and “becomes permanent action and gives birth to permanent organizations” (1971: 139).

    The terms “apparent” and “appearance” … are the assertion of the perishable nature of all ideological systems, side by side with the assertion that all [such] systems have an historical validity, and are necessary (“Man acquires consciousness of social relations in the field of ideology”: is not this an assertion of the necessity and validity of “appearances”?) (1971: 138)

    The parenthetical quotation is not a quotation at all, but an interpretive paraphrase of Marx’s claim in the 1859 Preface that the socially transformative conflict between the developed means of production and the existing relations of production comes to human consciousness and is fought out by people only in “legal, political, religious, artistic or philosophic – in short, ideological forms.”

    Again, Gramsci’s interpretive translation of Marx’s claim makes clear his distinctive inheritance of the Leninist insistence on ideological struggle. In stark contrast to Lukács’s “economism and class reductionism,” Gramsci understood “the ideological not in terms of mere ideas, but rather as a material ensemble of hegemonic apparatuses in civil society,” a set of institutions (Rehmann 2014: 117). More fundamentally, it was Lukács’s conception of expressive totality, with the commodity structure as the essence of modern society and proletarian labor as the essence of the essence, that reduced ideology to a pure consciousness manifested in (or deviating from) correct ideas, and it is Gramsci’s reassertion of the “necessity and validity of ‘appearances’” that restores to the ideological its specific diversity and its political relevance as a field of operations. The “field” or “terrain” of ideology is, for Gramsci and those who follow him, the “material matrix of affirmations and sanctions” in which different ideologies compete with, clash with, and reinforce one another, by recruiting and deploying agents (Therborn 1999: 33).

    The most important elaboration and development of Gramsci’s approach to ideology is the infamous theory of Althusser.[44] The most productive clarification and revision of Althusser’s theory is the criminally neglected[45] work of Göran Therborn. What emerges from this line of influence is not a new ideology critique, but rather a general theory of ideology as the space of reasons, the terrain where agency happens.[46] This theory is materialist, however, in that it understands normative beliefs not as motivating reasons for action but as retrospective, justificatory discourse. The reasons that motivate action are the institutionalized affirmations and sanctions that recruit or subjectify or qualify – more on those verbs in a second – agents.

    I find this theory fruitful, but I recognize that its payoff – even its intelligibility – is not immediately apparent. The aim of this final section is to arrive at intelligibility. I can only gesture here at potential payoff by way of indicating the lines of research this approach opens onto. Unlike the Frankfurt School’s approach, which points only in the direction of moral self-clarification, the post-Gramscian account opens quite naturally onto the empirical study of domination.

    One difficulty in discussing Althusser’s elaboration of the Gramscian account of ideology is that its reception has been massively overdetermined by the academic fights about structuralism and post-structuralism. On the one hand, many who were committed in one way or another to the explanatory priority of human agency took Althusser to be a structuralist and took structuralism to be identical with functionalism. As a result, Althusser was said to have “reduce[d] agency … to an ideological illusion,” such that, “individuals are not agents but rather raw material which ideology transforms into subjects ready to submit to their predestined role in the relations of production” (Callinicos 2006: 177–78).[47] On the other hand, those who were committed to following through the project of post-Althusserian French theory took Althusser to be too constrained by “the logic of conscience” implicit in Lacanian structuralism. According to this reading, Althusser’s account of ideological interpellation presupposes the subject’s “passionate complicity with law,” a complicity that at once conditions and limits the viability of critique, since “one cannot criticize too far the terms by which one’s existence is secured” (Butler 1997: 129). This pushes those like Butler in the direction of embracing “a willingness not to be – a critical desubjectivation – in order to expose the law as less powerful than it seems” (1997: 130).[48] One set of readers thought Althusser went way too far in the displacement of self-conscious and norm-directed human agency, while another set thought he did not go far enough. Both agreed, however, that he fell into functionalism. Both were wrong.

    Althusser’s account of ideology seems to be the reverse of “the social construction of reality.” For Althusser, the question is not, how do human agents create an objective world of social significance, but how does a structured, meaningful world call into being humans as agents? This interpellation framework puts structure first, and, therefore, when it confronts systems of domination, it seems prone to functionalism. If structures recruit their bearers by interpellating them as subjects, then the reproduction of the system seems to be secured by the structure recruiting just the bearers it needs.

    One of the signal contributions of Therborn’s The Ideology of Power and the Power of Ideology is recasting and developing Althusser’s argument so as to inoculate it against functionalism.[49] It accomplishes this in two ways. First, it is quite explicit about pluralizing ideologies, in the sense of insisting that “ruling-class ideological domination” is not the only ideological game in town, and that, moreover, “the ideological universe is not reducible to class ideologies” at all (Therborn 1999: 9, 26). Second, it specifically differentiates the “ego-ideology” and the “alter-ideology” that coexist in every positional ideology. I want to look at both of these moves more closely before stepping back to draw some lessons.

    Althusser motivated his investigation of ideology by asking the question of how capitalist society reproduces itself. It is in the context of this question that he introduces the “ideological state apparatuses” and begins to discuss the way they recruit and form individuals so as to make them ready to be bearers of the relations of production. However, the discussion of interpellation in the second part of his essay is not restricted to this perspective of the reproduction of an exploitative mode of production. Rather, he explicitly broadens the scope so as to consider ideology tout court, the ideology that “has no history,” as he says, “omnipresent, trans-historical, and therefore immutable in form” (Althusser 1972: 161). Nevertheless, this discussion takes place in the shadow of the discussion of social reproduction, and so it is easy to imagine that all ideology works to reproduce class societies.

    Therborn clearly and explicitly breaks with this presentation of the question. He is concerned, among other things, to show how Althusser’s conception of interpellation can illuminate both “the multidimensionality of ideologies” and “a crucial aspect of ideological struggles and ideological relations of force” (Therborn 1999: 27). Therborn claims that interpellation identifies “the dialectical character of all ideology” by articulating “the opposite senses of the same word ‘subject’ in the expression ‘the subject of king X (or the social order Y)’ and ‘the subject of history’” (1999: 16–17).

    He wants to move beyond this subject/subject (or subjection/subjectivation) pairing – which risks making social theory hinge on a pun – and prefers instead the subjection/qualification doublet. I think “qualification” ends up repeating the dialectical alternation entirely on its own, though. Ideology qualifies1 in the sense of picking out what sort of being one is by means of address. And, in the moment of qualifying the being of the addressee, ideology also qualifies2 the addressee to speak or act as what they are. The word agent, in fact, contains the same duality. An agent is both someone who acts under their own direction, and someone who carries out actions only on behalf of someone else, a principle. The principle-agent problem turns precisely on the fact that an agent in the second sense proves also to be an agent in the first sense.

    As Quill Kukla puts the point:

    On this account, because being a person involves having a specific normative status, becoming one involves the repetition of a mythical structure whereby we become bound in the proper way by being recognized and recognizing ourselves as already having been bound. If we do not do this, the claims made upon us, such as the demand implicit in a hail, will not get a grip on us. Recognizing the hail involves recognizing not just its presence but its legitimacy, which is inseparable from taking it as really aimed at me, and hence as already making a real claim on me in virtue of having identified me correctly. The recognition of legitimacy and the constitution of legitimacy (and likewise, to the extent that being a certain person is a normative status, the recognition of who we are and the constitution of who we are) occur together. (2000: 168)

    On the Althussser/Therborn account, ideology is happening when someone asks, “Can I talk to you, woman-to-woman?” And, since we also hail ourselves in various ways, ideology is happening when someone says, “As a student, I…” Ideology is also happening when we are disqualified in one way or another: e.g., “You’re no worker,” or “Why don’t you let the experts speak?”[50]

    Therborn seeks to add order to this general account by analytically distinguishing four “dimensions” that constitute “the fundamental forms of human subjectivity” – ways of being in the world – and thereby producing “a structural map of the universe of ideologies” (1999: 23, 22). [See table 1.] Ideology may dis/qualify us as: 1) members of the human world as such, 2) members of a given socio-historical world among others, 3) occupying a particular position within the human world as such, or 4) occupying a particular position within a given socio-historical world among others.

    Table 1: The universe of ideological interpellation

    Subjectivities of ‘in-the-world’ Subjectivities of ‘being’
    Existential Historical
    Inclusive 1.     Membership in the world as such (humanity, mortality, divinity, etc.) 2.     Membership in a given social world (exclusive inclusion: citizenship, nationhood, church, neighborhood, etc.)
    Positional 3.     Particular location in the world as such (age, gender, etc.) 4.     Particular location in a given social world (status, occupation, lifestyle, race, class, etc.)

     

    The lessons Therborn draws from this abstract structural map are almost perfectly consonant with Stuart Hall’s Gramsci-inspired concrete analysis of ideological struggles.[51] First, “the ideological universe is never reducible to class ideologies. Even in the most class-polarized and class-conscious societies, the other fundamental forms of human subjectivity coexist with class subjectivities,” and existential questions will always be addressed by existential ideologies (Therborn 1999: 26). Second, “class ideologies coexist” – and must coexist – “with inclusive-historical ideologies” that define, say, national or religious belonging” (1999: 27). Finally – and here he borrows language directly from Gramsci and Hall – “a crucial aspect of ideological struggles and of ideological relations of force is the articulation of a given type of ideology with others” (1999: 27).

    To illustrate with one of Hall’s examples:

    Thinking about the ideological articulation of ‘black’ clearly demands that we recognise its relations to issues of class, class ideologies, and class struggles, but in ways that do not reduce the specificity of race, of racist concepts and practices, as well as of anti-racist struggles as a potential field of ideological contestation. … Race and class are powerfully articulated with one another but they are not the same and, consequently, each is likely to both unite and divide. A black labouring class, exploited by capital, is able to begin to constitute its political unity, partly through the categories of class, but more significantly through the categories of race in this particular situation [South Africa]. One can see this only by recognising the necessary autonomy of the different movements in the South African political scene, and the capabilities of developing a common political struggle through the possible articulation of those elements, without assuming their necessary correspondence. (Hall 2016: 186–87)

    The plurality of ideologies cannot be eliminated, and the field of ideologies is crisscrossed with multiple lines of contest and opposition, but also with lines of support and interaction. In this context, the functionalist claim that ideology secures the reproduction of the exploitative relations of production loses its grip.[52] So, too, does the Leninist certainty that there is one struggle to which all the others reduce. The most you can say is that the reproduction of the relations of production is secured by the outcome, always provisional and contested, of various ideological struggles and on the basis of prevailing ideological relations of force.

    The second line pursued by Therborn is to explicitly acknowledge and analyze the distinction between ego- and alter-ideologies. Positional ideologies – including class ideologies – qualify their addressees as occupying one position among others in the world, and therefore necessarily relate their recipients to others, occupying other positions. But, even if we suppose for a moment a dyadic social world with only two positions, x and y, there is no reason to suppose that the ego-ideology of those in position x corresponds to the alter-ideology of those in position y. The boss’s self-image may diverge quite sharply from her employees’ image of her.

    This is critically important for thinking about ideology in systems of domination. The alter-ideology of those in the dominant position – what Albert Memmi analyzed as “the mythical portrait of the colonized” (1991: 123)[53] – may be at odds with the ego-ideology of the dominated. The attempt to subject/qualify the dominated by one set of interpellations will encounter a contrary attempt, among the dominated, to subject/qualify one another in different terms. The subaltern can speak, they overwhelmingly speak to one another, and how they address one another can never be reduced to how the dominant address them.

    The ritual practices of domination – parades, public apologies, ceremonies of magnificence, bowing and genuflection, etc. – constitute the public transcript of the ego- and alter-ideology of the dominant, while the ego- and alter-ideology of the dominated are a hidden transcript, to borrow the terms of James Scott (1990). This means that the ideologies of the dominant – the practices and discourses in which they hail both one another and their servants – are openly proclaimed and available for all to see. These practices of dis/qualification, however, do not reveal everything about the situation, since they are, precisely, the terms in which the dominant justify their dominance.[54] They must, in some sense, be “read against the grain” in order to release the knowledge they contain potentially (Kayes 1989). This intuition, arrived at by many travelers on many roads, has given rise to diverse and mutually incompatible methods of discourse analysis and interpretation, all of which strive to open up or inhabit “the perspective of the dominated” (Patterson 1982: 335).

    As Therborn points out, there is also, “inscribed in the asymmetry of domination,” a difference between the alter-ideology of the dominant and the alter-ideology of the dominated (1999: 28). Where the alter-ideology of the dominant is an image of the dominated that seeks to impose itself on them, to shape and control them, the alter-ideology of the dominated does not seek to control the dominant but to resist and/or evade them. Hence, it is not surprising that many of the attempts to break the seal on the ideologies of domination have turned very precisely to rebellion, resistance, and escape as sites for revealing, for instance, “the peasant as the maker of his own rebellion” (Guha 1983: 4).

    The post-Gramscian account of ideology, including especially Therborn’s analytical clarification of that account, gives us a theoretical matrix for thinking about this corpus of studies in a fruitful way, not only because it combats the tendency towards functionalism, but because it provides a new basis for thinking anew the intersection of domination and ideology. The risk of pluralizing ideology is that, in recognizing the pervasiveness and multifaceted character of ideology, one might simultaneously evacuate ideology of its stakes – or else invest every contest over dis/qualification with a moral urgency that is exhausting and fruitless. If everything is ideological, then ideological struggle becomes the night in which all cows are black. But by separating domination out from ideology, and tracing the specific ways in which relations of domination have a special set of effects on the ideological field, Therborn’s framework gives us the analytical tools necessary to focus on some ideological struggles rather than others.

    Therborn’s framework also confronts us with a problem, though. Insofar as the attempt to penetrate the dominant ideology is understood as the effort to discover and read the hidden transcript, the project of inquiry seems to be confined to peeling back one ideology in search of another. The ego- and alter-ideologies of the dominated – their standpoint, perspective, voice, and agency – may well be worth recovering, to whatever extent we can but, as ideological, these express, in Althusser’s phrase, an “imaginary relationship of individuals to their real conditions of existence” (1972: 162).

    Therborn himself wants to dismiss this phrase because it is redolent of the opposition “between science and ideology as such, true and false consciousness,” an opposition he thinks is “tied to a view of human motivation” according to which people are driven to act by real class interests, in relation to which ideology is merely epiphenomenal, illusory, “and as such ineffective (at least in the longer run)” (1999: 4, 8). I do not agree.

    Althusser’s distinction between ideology and science is analogous to Wilfrid Sellars’s distinction between normative facts and empirical facts.[55] Quill Kukla, whose attention to the similarities between Sellars and Althusser is groundbreaking, notes that “empirical facts, for Sellars, are in a sense always normative ‘all the way down,’ in the sense that they can make determinate, authoritative claims on us only when we take them as normatively related to other facts” (2000: 209). This is analogous to Althusser’s claim that “there is no practice [including, obviously, scientific practice] except by and in an ideology” (1972: 170). And yet Sellars wants to distinguish normative from empirical facts and Althusser wants to distinguish ideology from science. As Kukla clarifies, “to state a normative fact is not merely to describe a state of affairs, but rather to make a set of demands.”

    Standard examples like ‘killing is wrong’ are obvious cases; more interestingly, ‘p is evidence’ is a normative fact in a way that ‘p is green’ is not, even if we grant that the claim ‘p is green’ is only meaningful as placed within normative space. To say that ‘p is evidence’ is not just to report on a state of affairs, but to make a claim about what sort of authority p has. To say that ‘p is green’ commits us to various inferences and other claims and generally embeds us in the economy of epistemic authority, but it does not make a claim about this normative melee. (2000: 209–10; emphasis added)

    Adapting this to Althusser’s case, we can say that an ideological claim is about the “normative melee,” whereas a scientific claim is in but not about normative space. An ideological claim makes demands, whereas a scientific claim merely embeds its author and its reader in an economy of such demands without itself making any demands on them.

    This matters because Therborn’s recognition that domination is distinct from and influential upon ideologies implicitly acknowledges this same distinction. Varying Sellars’s distinction slightly, we can say that domination is a social fact, not a normative fact. To say that ‘x stands in a relation of domination to y’ is only meaningful within the space of reasons, and it is a claim about a relationship obtaining within the space of reasons, but it is not itself a normative claim. It makes no demands upon us. It does not tell us what stance we should take vis-à-vis this social fact. Domination is, in this way, a “normatively neutral” concept; the normative stance we take to an instance of domination “does not depend on the definition of domination itself,” but is based on our other normative commitments (Pansardi 2016: 94, n. 3).[56]

    That Therborn is committed to such a distinction is indicated by his retention of a materialist account of ideologies as always operating “in a material matrix of affirmations and sanctions.” He rightly insists that “the competition, coexistence, or conflict of different ideologies is dependent on the non-discursive matrices” within which they exist. The social facts regarding who can do what to whom at what cost are analytically distinct from the ideological significance of those facts, even if “all human activity is invested with meaning and all ideological interpellations have some kind of ‘material’ existence” (Therborn 1999: 33–34). Therborn’s practical commitment to a distinction between the order of ideology and the order of science is further indicated by his acceptance of two historical materialist hypotheses. First, all ideologies in class societies are themselves “bound up with and affected by different modes of class existence and are linked to and affected by different class ideologies.” Second, and more controversially, while “ideological conflicts and competition are (usually) not directly determined by class relations,” they are nonetheless “overdetermined by class relations” in the sense “that different classes select different forms of non-class ideologies and that class constellations of force limit the possibilities of ideological interrelationships and of ideological change” (1999: 38–39; emphasis added).

    The intricacies of these commitments can be left aside. What matters for present purposes is that the line of thinking about ideology that was inaugurated by Gramsci and developed by Althusser and Therborn is committed to an analytical distinction between social facts and ideological facts, or between our real social conditions and our imaginary relation to those conditions, even as it insists upon both the necessary permanence of ideology and the validity of the space of reasons within which we find ourselves and operate. This is not Marx and Engels’s critique of ideology as protagonism, though it is compatible with that critique. Neither is it the critique of ideology as false consciousness – whether this is opposed to class consciousness or to critical consciousness – since it is not the case that ideology is reducible to consciousness, and neither  is it the case that projects of self-emancipation are anything other than ideological projects.

    Gone, too, is the entire conception of overcoming or escaping a reified “second nature” into an unstructured and free space of reasons and norms. The space of reasons and norms is the terrain of ideology, the space in which we address one another and are addressed, in which we recruit one another to projects and are recruited. This space of reasons is both co-extensive with society and always structured or patterned by material social relations that can and must be identified and discussed in distinction from the space of reasons itself.

    The consequence of this shift emerges when Therborn criticizes political theory for continuously dealing with ideology within the frameworks of the legitimacy of government and the consent of the governed. As he argues, these frameworks are fundamentally rooted in “a subjectivist conception of history, according to which political processes are decided by unitary conscious subjects.” They are also essentially “idealist” – protagonist-ideological, one might add – in their complete separation of normative matters from material practices, and their assumption of “a simplistic, rationalist motivation of human beings” (Therborn 1999: 101–2). Against this focus on legitimacy and consent, Therborn insists that what is needed is a method of “normative evaluation” that applies itself “directly to the institutions of the regime, rather than to the way they are maintained”;  that is, to the “rights and powers” these institutions “grant, in practice, to different groups and classes in society,” and the sanctions they deploy in the enforcement and distribution of these rights and powers (1999: 110).

    It is to this task – studying and evaluating the rights and powers actually granted by social and political institutions – that critical social theory ought to turn. The fundamental question ought to be: “Who can do what to whom, at what cost?”

     

    William Clare Roberts is Associate Professor of Political Science at McGill University, in Montreal. He is the author of Marx’s Inferno: The Political Theory of Capital (2107). He is currently at work on two book manuscripts: The Radical Politics of Freedom: Domination, Ideology, and Self-Emancipation, and Universal Emancipation and History: The Making and Unmaking of ‘History From Below.’

     

    References

    Abercrombie, Nicholas, Stephen Hill, and Bryan S. Turner. 1980. The Dominant Ideology Thesis. Reprint edition. G. Allen & Unwin.

    Akselrod, Lyubov Isaakovna. 1914. “В ЗАЩИТУ ИДЕОЛОГИИ (In Defense of Ideology).” Sovlit.Org. 1914. http://sovlit.org/lia/Texts/LIA_V%20zashchitu%20ideologii.pdf.

    Althusser, Louis. 1972. Lenin and Philosophy, and Other Essays. Translated by Ben Brewster. New York: Monthly Review Press.

    Ascher, Abraham. 1988. The Revolution of 1905: Russia in Disarray. Vol. 1. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Augustine. 1960. City of God: Books 18.36-20. Translated by William Chase Greene. Vol. VI. Loeb Classical Library 416. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Aytac, Ugur, and Enzo Rossi. 2023. “Ideology Critique without Morality: A Radical Realist Approach.” American Political Science Review 117 (4): 1215–27.

    Barrett, Michèle. 1991. The Politics of Truth: From Marx to Foucault. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Benbow, William. 1832. Grand National Holiday and Congress of the Productive Classes, &c. London: Printed and published by the author.

    Berger, Peter L., and Thomas Luckmann. 1990. The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. New York: Anchor Books.

    Biko, Steve. 2002. I Write What I like: Selected Writings. Edited by Aelred Stubbs. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Bose, Anuja. 2023. “Vigilance as a Practice of Postcolonial Freedom.” American Political Science Review, September, 1–14.

    Bowman, Paul. 2021. “Ideology and Protagonism.” Eidgenossen (blog). August 22, 2021. https://eidgenossen.medium.com/ideology-and-protagonism-9e35598d389c.

    Butler, Judith. 1997. The Psychic Life of Power: Theories in Subjection. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Callinicos, Alex. 2006. Making History: Agency, Structure, and Change in Social Theory. 2nd ed. Historical Materialism. Leiden: Brill.

    Carling, Alan. 1993. “Analytical Marxism and Historical Materialism: The Debate on Social Evolution.” Science & Society 57 (April): 31–65.

    ———. 2002. “Analytical Marxism and the Debate on Social Evolution.” In Historical Materialism and Social Evolution, edited by Paul Blackledge and Graeme Kirkpatrick, 98–128. London: Palgrave Macmillan UK.

    Chibber, Vivek. 2022. The Class Matrix: Social Theory after the Cultural Turn. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Cooke, Maeve. 2006. “Resurrecting the Rationality of Ideology Critique: Reflections on Laclau on Ideology.” Constellations 13 (1): 4–20.

    Destutt de Tracy, Antoine Louis Claude. 2011. A Treatise on Political Economy. Edited by Jeremy Jennings. Translated by Thomas Jefferson. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    ———. 2015. Éléments d’Idéologie : Quatrième et Cinquième Parties – Traité de La Volonté et de Ses Effets. Paris: Ligaran Éditions.

    Dworkin, Andrea. 1983. Right-Wing Women. New York: Perigee Books.

    Eagleton, Terry. 1991. Ideology: An Introduction. London: Verso.

    Forst, Rainer. 2015. “Noumenal Power.” Journal of Political Philosophy 23 (2): 111–27.

    Freeden, Michael. 2003. Ideology: A Very Short Introduction. Very Short Introductions 95. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Frosini, Fabio. 2008. “Beyond the Crisis of Marxism: Gramsci’s Contested Legacy.” In Critical Companion to Contemporary Marxism, edited by Jacques Bidet and Stathis Kouvelakis, 663–79. Historical Materialism Book Series 16. Leiden: Brill.

    Garcia, Manon. 2021. We Are Not Born Submissive: How Patriarchy Shapes Women’s Lives. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    García-Alonso, Marta. 2013. “La Boétie and the Neo-Roman Conception of Freedom.” History of European Ideas 39: 317–34.

    Garnet, Henry Highland. 2001. “Address to the Slaves of the United States.” In Pamphlets of Protest: An Anthology of Early African-American Protest Literature, 1790–1860, edited by Richard Newman, Patrick Rael, and Philip Lapansky, 160–64. New York: Routledge.

    Garnsey, Peter. 1996. Ideas of Slavery from Aristotle to Augustine. The W.B. Stanford Memorial Lectures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Gaus, Gerald F. 1997. “On the Difficult Virtue of Minding One’s Own Business: Towards the Political Rehabilitation of Ebenezer Scrooge.” The Philosopher 5: 24–28.

    Geuss, Raymond. 1981. The Idea of a Critical Theory: Habermas and the Frankfurt School. Modern European Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Gramsci, Antonio. 1971. Selections from the Prison Notebooks. Translated by Quintin Hoare and Geoffrey Nowell Smith. New York: International Publishers.

    Guha, Ranajit. 1983. Elementary Aspects of Peasant Insurgency in Colonial India. Delhi: Oxford University Press.

    Habermas, Jürgen. 1973. Theory and Practice. Translated by John Viertel. Boston: Beacon Press.

    ———. 1979. Communication and the Evolution of Society. Translated by Thomas McCarthy. Boston: Beacon Press.

    ———. 1987. The Theory of Communicative Action: A Critique of Functionalist Reason. Translated by Thomas McCarthy. Vol. 2. 2 vols. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Haider, Asad. 2018. Mistaken Identity: Race and Class in the Age of Trump. London: Verso.

    Hall, Stuart. 2016. Cultural Studies 1983: A Theoretical History. Edited by Jennifer Daryl Slack and Lawrence Grossberg. Stuart Hall, Selected Writings. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 2013. Phenomenology of Spirit. Edited by John N. Findlay. Translated by A. V. Miller. Reprint. Oxford Paperbacks. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Hickman, Jared. 2016. Black Prometheus: Race and Radicalism in the Age of Atlantic Slavery. Oxford University Press.

    Horkheimer, Max. 1982. Critical Theory: Selected Essays. New York: Continuum Publishing Corp.

    Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor W. Adorno. 2002. Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments. Edited by Gunzelin Schmid Noerr. Translated by Edmund Jephcott. Cultural Memory in the Present. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Jaeggi, Rahel. 2009. “Rethinking Ideology.” In New Waves in Political Philosophy, edited by Boudewijn de Bruin and Christopher F. Zurn, 63–86. London: Palgrave Macmillan UK.

    Johnson, Sarah. 2022. “Farewell to The German Ideology.” Journal of the History of Ideas 83 (1): 143–70.

    Kayes, Jamie Barlowe. 1989. “Reading against the Grain: The Powers and Limits of Feminist Criticism of American Narratives.” The Journal of Narrative Technique 19 (1): 130–40.

    Kukla, Rebecca. 2000. “Myth, Memory and Misrecognition in Sellars’ ‘Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind.’” Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition 101 (2/3): 161–211.

    La Boétie, Étienne De. 2012. Discourse on Voluntary Servitude. Translated by James B. Atkinson and David Sices. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Lafont, Cristina. 2023. “The Return of the Critique of Ideologies.” Constellations 30 (4): 390–94.

    Lichtheim, George. 1965. “The Concept of Ideology.” History and Theory 4 (2): 164–95.

    Lih, Lars T. 2008. Lenin Rediscovered: What Is to Be Done? In Context. Historical Materialism Book Series. Chicago: Haymarket Books.

    Lukács, György. 1971. History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics. Translated by Rodney Livingstone. London: Merlin Press.

    ———. 1972. Tactics and Ethics: Political Writings, 1919-29. Edited by Rodney Livingstone. Translated by Michael McColgan. London: New Left Books.

    Mannheim, Karl. 2015. Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge. Translated by Louis Wirth and Edward A. Shils. Mansfield Centre: Martino Publishing.

    Marx, Karl. 1976. Capital: A Critique of Political Economy. Translated by Ben Fowkes. Vol. 1. London: Penguin.

    Marx, Karl. 2009. Gesamtausgabe (MEGA). Karl Marx: Werke, Artikel, Entwürfe. März 1843 bis August 1844. Edited by Ileana Bauer, Bernhard Dohm, and Inge Taubert. Vol. I/2. Gesamtausgabe (MEGA). Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

    Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels. 1981. Gesamtausgabe (MEGA). Karl Marx und Friedrich Engels: Exzerpte und Notizen, 1843 bis Januar 1845. Edited by Nelly Rumjanzewa. Vol. IV/2. Gesamtausgabe (MEGA). Berlin: Dietz Verlag.

    ———. 2017. Gesamtausgabe (MEGA). Karl Marx und Friedrich Engels: Deutsche Ideologie Manuskripte und Drucke. Edited by Ulrich Pagel, Gerald Hubmann, and Christine Weckwerth. Vol. I/5. Gesamtausgabe (MEGA). Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

    Memmi, Albert. 1991. The Colonizer and the Colonized. Translated by Howard Greenfield. Expanded ed. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Mills, Charles W. 1992. “‘Ideology’ in Marx and Engels’ Revisited and Revised.” Philosophical Forum 23 (4): 301–28.

    Mills, Charles W., and Danny Goldstick. 1989. “A New Old Meaning of ‘Ideology.’” Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review 28 (3): 417–32.

    Moore, Barrington. 1978. Injustice: The Social Bases of Obedience and Revolt. White Plains: M.E. Sharpe.

    Newman, Saul. 2022. “La Boétie and Republican Liberty: Voluntary Servitude and Non-Domination.” European Journal of Political Theory 21 (1): 134–54.

    Nizalowska, Ewa. 2022. “Theory as Translation: Gramsci’s Reading of Machiavelli and Marx.” Montreal: McGill University.

    Nyquist, Mary. 2015. Arbitrary Rule: Slavery, Tyranny, and the Power of Life and Death.

    Origenes. 1982. Homilies on Genesis and Exodus. Translated by Ronald E. Heine. The Fathers of the Church 71. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press

    Pansardi, Pamela. 2016. “Democracy, domination and the distribution of power: Substantive Political Equality as a Procedural Requirement.” Revue internationale de philosophie 275 (1): 91–108.

    Patterson, Orlando. 1982. Slavery and Social Death: A Comparative Study. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Pinsker, Leon. 1906. Auto-Emancipation. Translated by D.S. Blondheim. New York: The Maccabaean Publishing Company.

    Plato. 2016. The Republic of Plato. Translated by Allan Bloom. 3rd ed. Boulder: Basic Books.

    Przeworski, Adam. 1985. Capitalism and Social Democracy. Studies in Marxism and Social Theory. Cambridge; Paris: Cambridge University Press; Editions de la Maison des sciences de l’homme.

    Ramsay, Peter. 2022. “Vulnerability as Ideology.” The Northern Star. 2022. https://thenorthernstar.online/analysis/vulnerability-as-ideology-i/.

    Rehmann, Jan. 2014. Theories of Ideology: The Powers of Alienation and Subjection. Historical Materialism Book Series. Chicago: Haymarket Books.

    Roberts, Jennifer Tolbert. 2011. Athens on Trial: The Antidemocratic Tradition in Western Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Rosen, Michael. 1996. On Voluntary Servitude: False Consciousness and the Theory of Ideology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Rudé, George F. E. 1980. Ideology and Popular Protest. 1st American ed. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Sankaran, Kirun. 2020. “What’s New in the New Ideology Critique?” Philosophical Studies 177 (5): 1441–62.

    Scott, James C. 1987. Weapons of the Weak: Everyday Forms of Peasant Resistance. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    ———. 1990. Domination and the Arts of Resistance: Hidden Transcripts. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    ———. 2008. Seeing like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition Have Failed. Yale Agrarian Studies. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Seneca, Lucius Annaeus. 1932. Moral Essays, Volume II: De Consolatione Ad Marciam. De Vita Beata. De Otio. De Tranquillitate Animi. De Brevitate Vitae. De Consolatione Ad Polybium. De Consolatione Ad Helviam. Translated by John W. Basore. Loeb Classical Library 254. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Shaw, William H. 1989. “Ruling Ideas.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplementary Volume 15: 425–48.

    Smith, Adam. 1976. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Edited by Edwin Cannan. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Therborn, Göran. 1999. The Ideology of Power and the Power of Ideology. Verso Classics ed. London: Verso.

    Thomas, Peter D. 2009. The Gramscian Moment: Philosophy, Hegemony and Marxism. Leiden: Brill.

    Thompson, E. P. 1978. The Poverty of Theory & Other Essays. New York: Monthly Review Press.

    Wendling, Amy E. 2012. The Ruling Ideas: Bourgeois Political Concepts. Blue Ridge Summit: Lexington Books/Fortress Academic.

     

    [1] Lyubov Isaakovna Akselrod (1914). I would like to thank two anonymous referees, and well as Christian Thorne, for their comments and questions, which have made this essay stronger than it would otherwise have been. I also owe a great debt to the students of my seminar in the winter of 2022, without whom I would not have been able to do this work.

    [2] It has been over forty years since Abercrombie, Hill, and Turner wrote: “It is widely agreed that the notion of ‘ideology’ has given rise to more analytical and conceptual difficulties than almost any other term in the social sciences. The term has suffered many demolitions and reconstitutions” (1980: 187). In the intervening decades, demolitions and reconstitutions have continued apace, and analytical and conceptual difficulties have continued to accumulate.

    [3] This also includes the early Zionists, whose desire for national self-emancipation could not take the form of an anti-colonialism, since they lacked a territorial base, but took instead the form of a colonialism. Leon Pinsker argued that, for Jews, the “future will remain insecure and precarious unless a radical change in our position is made. This change cannot be brought about by the civil emancipation of the Jews in this or that state, but only by the auto-emancipation of the Jewish people as a nation, the foundation of a colonial community belonging to the Jews, which is some day to become our inalienable home, our country” (1906: 15)

    [4] For a searching investigation of voluntary submission in the history and present of feminist and political theory, see Garcia (2021).

    [5] For recent statements, pro and contra, of the “classical” conception of ideology critique, see Lafont (2023) and Sankaran (2020), respectively.

    [6] Dworkin comes the closest. Her examination of anti-feminism among women is clearly motivated by her commitment to the self-emancipation of women, but this motivating commitment is not itself brought reflexively into her study.

    [7] This is clear from the source texts collected in Garnsey (1996).

    [8] See, however, Origen’s Homily on Genesis, where the forcible bondage of the Hebrews in Egypt is contrasted to the bondage of the Egyptians themselves. The Egyptians, Origen claims, “are prone to a degenerate life and quickly sink to every slavery of the vices,” a deficit he attributes to their descent from Ham and Canaan. This is a “voluntary bondage,” and, therefore, the divine Law does not “entertain concern for Egyptian freedom” (Origenes 1982: 16.1). The voluntary servitude of the Egyptians is an original and perpetual state, therefore, a manifest sign of their fitness for natural slavery. This approach is further codified in Augustine’s dictum that “the prime cause of slavery … is sin” (1960: 19.15).

    [9] See Nyquist (2015, chap. 2).

    [10] In this, he follows the earlier Italians, who “preferred the governments of Venice and Sparta to those of Florence and Athens, and the reasons they alleged were fairly consistent: Venetian and Spartan stability were preferable to the constant mutations of Florentine and Athenian government, and a mixed constitution was inherently more durable than one in which the supreme power is vested in the people” (Roberts 2011: 129).

    [11] See García-Alonso (2013), who argues that La Boétie’s position is close to Harrington’s, and that he saw an empire of law, protected by a senate of aristocrats, as the guarantor of political liberty against both tyranny and corruption (patronage).

    [12]  Or of “five or six,” or of  “six.” There is a fatal indeterminacy and perhaps an even more fatal inflation at work in La Boétie’s causal story. It is impossible to say exactly how many voluntary servants there are, and there may always be one more than you thought. Eternal vigilance, of course, is the price of liberty, but eternal suspicion may be the only modality of vigilance. There is a fairly direct line, then, between La Boétie’s theory of voluntary servitude and Robespierre’s practice of revolutionary virtue. On attempts by postcolonial statesmen to arrest this slide from vigilance into suspicion and distrust, see Bose (2023).

    [13] This is contrary to the wishes of some readers of an anarchist inclination; see, e.g., Newman (2022).

    [14] I have added the emphasis and modified the translation; compare Destutt de Tracy (2015: 284). In French, conscience means both conscience and consciousness, but Destutt de Tracy is not referring to a derangement of our moral sense but to a distortion of our broader awareness of our selves and our world.

    [15] I have modified the translation here; besoin, translated as “want” by Jefferson in keeping with English usage in the early nineteenth century, should be understood in the more emphatic sense of “need.”

    [16] This essay originally appeared in an Australian magazine, The Philosopher: A Magazine for Free Spirits, but the only version I can find anymore is the one published on Gaus’s website. My citations will, therefore, be of this version, which has its own pagination.

    [17] See also Lichtheim, who says simply that Marx and Engels “shared Napoleon’s disdain for them [the idéologistes]” (1965: 166).

    [18] It is Charles Mills who pioneered this interpretation (1992; anticipated by Mills and Goldstick 1989); I have also been guided in my reading of Marx and Engels by Bowman (2021).

    [19] Marx’s extracts can be found in Marx and Engels (1981, IV/2: 489–92).

    [20] It was more likely meant to be the statement of purpose for a journal on the lines of the defunct Deutsch-Französischen Jahrbücher (Johnson 2022).

    [21] I am not necessarily adopting Bowman’s analysis of protagonism whole cloth, however, though it has much to recommend it. We differ somewhat in our analyses of the superstructure, differences which will come out below.

    [22] No one has done more to flesh out this basic element of historical materialism that Alan Carling (1993; 2002).

    [23] For a representative example in an otherwise careful parsing of this passage, see Barrett (1991: 9–10; see also Shaw 1989).

    [24] Scott’s anarchist sympathies show themselves in his suspicion that trying to convince people to do something they don’t already want to do is, ipso facto, authoritarian.

    [25] This was the so-called “I. Feuerbach” section, still the most famous part of the manuscripts.

    [26] The role of translation in Gramsci’s prison writings, both as an activity and as a concept, has been examined by Nizalowska (2022).

    [27] On the Russian word underlying discussion of “spontaneity” (stikhiinost), and why it could better be rendered as “elemental-ness,” see Lih (2008: 616–28).

    [28] Zubatov was a former radical who became head of the Moscow Okhrana, from which perch he spearheaded a program of legal, police-led unions with the intent of demonstrating that the workers could gain more from working with the tsar than trying to overthrow him.

    [29] In Lih (2008: 709–10; translation modified).

    [30] Workers’ and soldiers’ councils also took over the administration of many cities, but without moving in a communist direction. Max Weber participated in the Heidelberg workers’ council, for example.

    [31] The line of argument running from What Is to Be Done? to Lukács’s 1919-23 writings indicates how misleading is Vivek Chibber’s claim that “Classical Marxism confidently asserted that capitalism’s own logic would lead inexorably to the organization of the working class and the overthrow of the system. … This theory, derived from Marx and Lenin, … rested on the assumption that forms of consciousness – of self-identification – would emerge within labor sooner or later, even if the path was a torturous one” (2022: 78). Chibber associates the turn to ideology with mid-century and New Left accounts of the integration of the working class into consumer culture. In fact, it was already fully developed and explicit in the classical Marxism of the Second International. It was Lyubov Isaakovna Axelrod (AKA “Orthodox”) – a committed partisan of Plekhanov, the archetypical font of the objective necessity of the proletarian revolution and the movement to socialism – who wrote “In Defense of Ideology” in Iskra in 1914.

    [32] “The effects of the division of labour, in the general business of society, will be more easily understood, by considering in what manner it operates in some particular manufactures. It is commonly supposed to be carried furthest in some very trifling ones; not perhaps that it really is carried further in them than in others of more importance: but in those trifling manufactures which are destined to supply the small wants of but a small number of people, the whole number of workmen must necessarily be small; and those employed in every different branch of the work can often be collected into the same workhouse, and placed at once under the view of the spectator. In those great manufactures, on the contrary, which are destined to supply the great wants of the great body of the people, every different branch of the work employs so great a number of workmen, that it is impossible to collect them all into the same workhouse. We can seldom see more, at one time, than those employed in one single branch. Though in such manufactures, therefore, the work may really be divided into a much greater number of parts, than in those of a more trifling nature, the division is not near so obvious, and has accordingly been much less observed” (Smith 1976: I.1).

    [33] Lukács’s argument here ignores Marx’s criticism of Smith on this point: the division of labor in the factory is not the same as the social division of labor, precisely because workers in a factory do not exchange their products with one another (see Marx 1976, chap. 14).

    [34] The extent to which Lukács is simply overwriting the preface to Hegel’s Phenomenology is remarkable. He has internalized Hegel’s claim that “the truth is the whole” (2013: §20), wedded this to the idea that Capital is socialism reduced to a science, and birthed from these the notion that the proletarian who comprehends the critique of political economy gains thereby a class consciousness that is merely the essential nature of humanity’s self-creation reaching its completeness through the process of its own development. “Of the Absolute,” Hegel wrote, “it must be said that it is essentially a result, that only at the end is it what it is in very truth; and just in that consists its nature, which is to be actual, subject, or self-becoming, self-development” (2013: §20). Lukács takes the absolute to be humanity itself, takes the end to be communism, and takes the self-becoming of this subject to be the proletariat becoming class conscious.

    [35] Lukács is quoting Lenin, “A Great Beginning.”

    [36] The phrase was coined by Berger and Luckmann (1990), but the way had already been charted by Mannheim (2015).

    [37] Contra Horkheimer (1982: 209).

    [38] This is a controversial judgment among partisans of early critical theory. However, I think it is at least plausible, and provides a defensible if not a complete picture.

    [39] “Illegitimate domination also meets with consent [Zustimmung], else it would not be able to last. (One need only recall those days in which great masses of people came together in the squares and on the streets, without being pressured to do so [ohne Pression], in order to acclaim ein Reich, ein Volk, ein Führer – was that an expression of anything other than a non-theoretical, average norm-consciousness?)” (Habermas 1979: 202; translation modified). The notion that mass enthusiasm and an absence of social pressure can coexist will not bear scrutiny.

    [40] In Rainer Forst’s version of the argument, “such structures are not ‘norm-free;’ rather the norms and justifications they rest on allow for certain orms of strategic action that disregard traditional and ethical norms” (2015: 119).

    [41] This also seems to be the presupposition of Rahel Jaeggi’s rethinking of ideology and ideology critique, although she is more equivocal. According to Jaeggi, ideological versions of ideals like freedom and equality take hold of practices – her examples are labor contracts and other forms of exploitative exchange – and twist or distort them so that they produce the opposite of the proclaimed norms of freedom and equality. Jaeggi concludes, therefore, that ideological “norms (as in the above-mentioned case, the values of freedom and equality that are constitutive for civil society) are effective, but as effective factors they have become inconsistent or deficient” (2009: 75). Jaeggi’s position, therefore, seems to be somewhat distinct from the Frankfurt School position reconstructed by Geuss, but it may be a distinction without a difference. False consciousness does not necessarily motivate the formation of practices, since it may instead originate in attempts to justify or rationalize existing practices. However, once ideological justifications exist, they shape or reconstruct the practices from which they emerged, and are effective insofar as they make the practices into engines for producing the opposite of the declared justificatory values. Ideology has rebuilt the objective, institutional world, and that world will not be torn down by ideology critique alone, but ideology critique is a prerequisite to that tearing down, just as ideology was a motivating factor in the reconstructing of the world.

    [42] The more parsimonious “radical realist” approach to ideology critique proposed by Aytac and Rossi, despite its debt to Geuss, may avoid this implicit reference to a counterfactual horizon of perfect knowledge and freedom, if only by eschewing any reference to totality in favor of a pragmatic claim about the epistemic faults typical of self-justifying power (2023).

    [43] These notes were part of The Modern Prince and Other Essays, a selection from the Quaderni published by International Publishers in 1957. They were also included in the collection of Gramsci’s prison notebooks published by Les Éditions Sociales in 1959. These two collections were the primary means of access to Gramsci’s writings in the anglophone and francophone worlds through the 1960s.

    [44] Althusser’s obvious and repeated criticisms of aspects of (the received version of) Gramsci’s theory for a long time created the impression that the two were “utterly incompatible” (Frosini 2008: 669; see also Thomas 2009).

    [45] In political theory, at least.

    [46] This is not the standard interpretation of Althusser, but neither is it unprecedented (see Kukla 2000).

    [47] Callinicos echoes arguments going back to Thompson (1978).

    [48] This argument has been important for a certain critique of identity politics (see Haider 2018). It also reveals, I think, Butler’s affinities with Adorno and Horkheimer’s critical theory.

    [49] This does not mean the accusation will not be made. Callinicos, for example, thinks that Therborn’s reconstruction is just as Parsonian as Althusser’s original, and that, “for Therborn, social actors are not agents, able to pursue their own goals, but are rather social constructs, the passive bearers of social relations” (2006: 146). My own argument in this section should put this accusation to rest.

    [50] My examples all use linguistic interpellations, but this is solely for the ease and brevity with which these can be invoked. Ritualized or institutionalized practices often require lengthy description to be identified.

    [51] However, it must be noted that, when Hall retreats to more abstract, general propositions about ideology he can occasionally sound very much like a student of the Frankfurt School.

    [52] Which is, in fact, precisely what Althusser affirmed at the end of his essay: “the State and its Apparatuses only have meaning from the point of view of the class struggle, as an apparatus of class struggle ensuring class oppression and guaranteeing the conditions of exploitation and its reproduction. But there is no class struggle without antagonistic classes. Whoever says class struggle of the ruling class says resistance, revolt, and class struggle of the ruled class” (1972: 184).

    [53] Memmi’s study is intriguing in part because, beginning from phenomenological premises, it approaches, asymptotically, the structuralist analysis of ideology found in Althusser and Therborn.

    [54] This is consonant with the argument of Aytac and Rossi (2023).

    [55] This is an analogy, not an identity. Althusser denies that science is empirical, and nothing I say about the similarities between his procedure and that of Sellars should be taken to imply attributing empiricism to Althusser.

    [56] This is very much contrary to the lesson drawn within the Frankfurt School, where domination names “cases of unjustifiable asymmetrical social relations which rest on a closing off of the space of justifications such that these relations appear as legitimate, natural, God-given, or in any way unalterable” (Forst 2015: 125). Forst has all the resources necessary in his conception of noumenal power to recognize that domination never leaves or closes off the space of reasons, but is unable to draw on those resources because of his single-minded focus on the exercise of power, rather than on power itself.

  • Hortense Spillers awarded honorary degree

    Hortense Spillers awarded honorary degree

    b2o is pleased to announce that our fellow bounder, Hortense Spillers, has been awarded an honorary degree of Doctor of Humanities by Yale University in recognition of her “pioneering achievement or exemplary contribution to the common good”. As the citation puts it:

    Inspiring Black feminist theorist and critic, your foundational work, embedded in your deep historical and literary knowledge, challenges received thought and provides us a profound understanding of how race and gender shape the modern world. In three books and dozens of essays, you rewrite the American grammar book, claiming the insurgent ground as you revolutionize how we consider and write about our nation’s history and culture. Pioneering thinker, we celebrate the marvels of your inventiveness, and your enduring contributions to letters, as we proudly confer on you the degree of Doctor of Humanities.

    Please join us in congratulating Hortense on a recognition that is well-deserved!

    boundary 2 recently published a dossier on Hortense’s work that was edited by Paul Bové.

  • Matthew Potolsky–Decadent Style for Critical Finance Scholars: A Response to Signe Leth Gammelgaard

    Matthew Potolsky–Decadent Style for Critical Finance Scholars: A Response to Signe Leth Gammelgaard

    This response was published as part of the b2o review‘s “Finance and Fiction” dossier.

    Matthew Potolsky–Decadent Style for Critical Finance Scholars: A Response to Signe Leth Gammelgaard

    Signe Leth Gammelgaard’s “Flowers Without Meaning: Literary Decadence as Finance Aesthetics” rides a wave of work from the last twenty years or so that draws upon the longue durée history of capitalism to contextualize cultural production in innovatively materialist terms. Broadening its vision from the durable leftist influences of the Frankfurt School, Pierre Bourdieu, and Louis Althusser, as well as the deconstructive New Economic Criticism of the 1990s, this scholarship supplements questions of commodity culture, symbolic capital, ideology, and the nature of value with attention to global trade and conquest, modes of production, and the history of economic crises, often drawing on world-systems theory and theories of uneven and combined development as well. One keynote of this turn is the concept of financialization—perhaps most closely associated with the work of the economic historian Giovanni Arrighi—which directs special attention to the power of the financial industry and finance as such in the culture at large.

    The most impressive recent work on financialization has tended to focus on literature of the 1980s and after, a period in which finance capital grew in power and influence at a historically unprecedented rate. But Arrighi, drawing on the longue durée studies of global capitalism by Fernand Braudel, sees financialization as recurrent feature of capitalist development, and therefore as one that has marked earlier periods as well. In her essay, Gammelgaard notes that the European fin de siècle was just such a moment and proposes that we can gain insight into the decadent aesthetic of the 1880s and 1890s by seeing it as manifestly a product of the financialized age. This is a claim with which I agree, and which I have been exploring in different terms in my current book project. In this response, I want to highlight the value of the approach Gammelgaard sketches in her essay and reframe her argument in ways that, to my mind, even better comport with how late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century writers understood both decadence and finance capital. My largest claim will be that Gammelgaard’s account of decadent aesthetics should also be applied to the conceptual history of finance capitalism. Scholars of financialization can learn as much from decadence as scholars of decadence can learn from the literature on financialization.

    Let me begin by briefly summarizing Arrighi’s argument to highlight the importance of the fin de siècle to his conception of financialization and economic cycles more generally. Arrighi argues in The Long Twentieth Century that the history of capitalism has been defined by “cycles of accumulation,” in which a succession of hegemonic centers of global economic activity rise and fall as they pass from periods of material expansion, when these centers invest chiefly in production and trade networks, to periods of financial expansion, when they turn increasingly to banking, credit, and speculation. The end of each cycle foretells a shift in political hegemony from one world city, region, or empire to another. Genoa gives way to Amsterdam, which gives way to London, which gives way to New York. At the beginning of each cycle, what Arrighi calls a “long century,” technological developments, access to newly valuable natural resources, or political innovations propel a new region to productive supremacy. That supremacy eventually underwrites a new cycle of financial supremacy, during which money, going abroad in search of greater profit, leads to the decline of the current hegemon and funds the rise of another.

    As Arrighi’s history makes clear, and as Gammelgaard perceptively notes, the end of the nineteenth century was a period of financial supremacy, in which dramatic capital accumulation temporarily ensured British and European hegemony over the globe. Arrighi calls such recurrent periods “signal crises,” or, evocatively alluding to the fin de siècle and following Braudel, belles époques. The years after 1870 in Europe were marked by a succession of banking crises, stock-market crashes, and the so-called Long Depression, as well as by rampant speculation in overseas colonies and in large infrastructure projects like railways and canals. Gammelgaard accordingly reads Joris-Karl Huysmans’s classic 1884 decadent novel À rebours as a response to  economic reality that, despite its celebration of aesthetic withdrawal, is no less astute in its depiction of the financialized culture than stock-exchange novels from the period, like Anthony Trollope’s The Way We Live Now (1875) and Émile Zola’s L’Argent (1891).[1] Highlighting Huysmans’s descriptions of exotic flowers and the Latin language, Gammelgaard connects the novel with two coeval intellectual developments—Saussure’s structural linguistics and William Stanley Jevons marginal revolution in economics—that also point to a crisis of signification that reflects the abstracting character of finance capital.[2] Yet, while Saussure and Jevons lean into that abstracting character, Huysmans undertakes a kind of rear-guard action by insisting on the sensory and material, as if, Gammelgaard writes, he were “trying to figure out what to do with a materiality that can no longer really be understood through the models we know.”

    I find this claim compelling, though to my mind it leaves perhaps the crucial question posed by the essay largely unanswered: what is it about the concept, history, or aesthetics of decadence that allows it to speak so precisely to the conditions of financialization? Many other movements in the period were immersed in sensuality (impressionism) or fascinated with images of cultural disintegration (naturalism), so these characteristics do not obviously set decadence apart. Writers like Trollope and Zola confronted the effects of late-century financialization more directly, and critics like John Ruskin pilloried bourgeois capitalism in much more incisive ways than the decadents did. Indeed, decadent writers rarely concern themselves the financial life of their characters, though matters of wealth, debt, credit, and investment do arise in their works. So, what does decadence offer that other contemporary writers and artists do not?

    I want to offer two answers to this question. The first emerges from the literature on financialization itself. Since its earliest conceptualization, the notion of finance capital has been closely and persistently associated with the sense of lateness and decline. In the third volume of Capital, Marx casts finance as “the most superficial and fetishized form” of capital—a putative endpoint, in which normatively social (if alienated) relations are pushed to distorted lengths (1981, 515). Later theorists of finance capital like Rudolf Hilferding and Vladimir Lenin explicitly use the language of decadence to describe the phenomenon. In Imperialism: The Last Stage of Capitalism, Lenin describes finance as capitalism that has “grown ripe, over-ripe and rotten” (1917, 128). The word “last” (высшая) in his title is bitingly ironic in Russian, suggesting not just the end of a temporal sequence but also the characteristically decadent qualities of excess, exorbitance, and overrefinement. Arrighi, as we have seen, associates financialization with the decline of hegemonic regions, and draws his name for periods of signal crisis from the fin de siècle. In a passage that Arrighi cites as the inspiration for his project, Braudel calls belles époques “a sign of autumn,” an image that draws from the store of decadent tropes (1984, 246).

    Decadence, then, is not only an aesthetic of financialization, as Gammelgaard shows, but is also part of the received conceptual framework for describing finance capital, which emerges as a manifestly decadent object. Both before and after the fin de siècle, commentators have drawn upon the concept to explain the rapid changes in the class system and generalized sense of historical transition that characterizes signal crises. The most important modern theorist of cultural decadence, the Baron de Montesquieu, wrote his influential Considerations on the Causes of the Greatness of the Romans and their Decline (1734) in the wake of the so-called Financial Revolution in England, which created the Bank of England and authorized the sale of government bonds, and little more than a decade after the ruinous South Sea Bubble of 1721. In 1796, Thomas Paine published a pamphlet entitled The Decline and Fall of the English System of Finance that took aim at excessive government borrowing. Braudel’s studies of capitalist economic cycles were written during the signal crisis of the 1970s, when contemporary regimes of finance began to emerge. The pattern also holds true for our contemporary era of financialization, as in works like The Hunger Games series (2008-10), where the capitol of Panem evokes decadent Rome in both its name (panem et circenses) and in the stereotypically decadent ways of its residents. The titular protagonist of Glen Duncan’s The Last Werewolf (2011) is modeled in large part on decadent characters like Des Esseintes.

    We can draw two salient points from the persistent copresence of decadence and finance. Decadence, to begin with, provides a durable rhetoric and set of historical examples (above all, imperial Rome) for describing the excesses inherent to moments of financialization. As Montesquieu writes in his Cahiers: “in empires, nothing comes closer to decadence than great prosperity” (1951, 82). More significantly, though, it is historical concepts like decadence that allow critics to see signal crises as characteristic and recurring features of history, and not just as random accidents, signs of divine judgment, or evidence of human perversity. Tracing its lineage to cyclical theories of political history from antiquity and early modernity (Polybius, Machiavelli, Vico), the notion of decadence encourages commentators to assimilate present crises to past ones.[3] So, while financialization helps us historicize decadence, decadence also helps us historicize theories of financialization. In particular, it helps us recognize the ways in which such theories persistently frame rapid capital accumulation in terms of a familiar narrative of rise and decline. Decadence here is a cognitive map—shared by commentators on the left and the right—which interprets financialization in moral, affective, and historical terms. Finance capital is at once natural and perverse, the epitome and the exception, its demise both inevitable and richly deserved.

    The second answer to the question of why decadence would emerge as a key finance aesthetic during the belle époque of the nineteenth century can be found in the aesthetics of decadence itself. Although scholars have tended to associate financialization with postmodernism, decadence offers an even more apposite model. Gammelgaard directs us to the decadent fascination with the sensual, material, and hedonistic, which she sees as a response to the loss of meaning under the regime of finance. But there are many other ways in which decadence might be seen to thematize the logic of financialization. Consider the centrality of fiction, artifice, and the lie in decadent aesthetics. In his 1890 dialogue “The Decay of Lying,” Oscar Wilde argues that reality is the “solvent that breaks up Art, the enemy that lays waste to her house” (2007, 83). “Art finds her own perfection within,” he writes, “and not outside of, herself. She is not to be judged by any external standard of resemblance” (2007, 89). It is not difficult see a parallel between Wilde’s celebration of artifice and the characterization of finance as “fictitious” or “imaginary,” an entity opposed to what has long been termed the “real economy.” Finance, according to this pervasive opposition, is the unnatural product of art and human ingenuity, not of genuine human labor. Rather than lamenting such an apparent loss of materiality, decadent writers like Wilde parodically lean into it. They criticize novelistic realism for its retrograde commitment to fact and celebrate figures like the dandy, who treats life as a work of art. As Huysmans writes: “artifice was considered by Des Esseintes to be the distinctive mark of human genius. Nature, he used to say, has had her day” (2003, 22). He compares landscapes and sunsets to unimaginative tradesmen and shopkeepers—dealers in the wares of the “real economy.” The very difference between the “real” and the “artificial” that is foundational to traditional definitions of finance capital becomes an object of contemplation. By perversely celebrating art over nature, writers like Wilde and Huysmans thus anticipate Laura Finch’s observation that “The fictionality of finance is, of course, a fiction itself” (2015, 732).

    The decadent interest in collecting and collections, which scholars have long tied to nineteenth-century consumerism, might also be understood as a reflection on financial accumulation. The sheer materiality of a collection offers more support to Gammelgaard’s claim that decadence challenges the abstractions of finance capital. But collections evoke the logic of financialization on a different level as well. Joshua Clover has suggested that financialization engenders an “autumnal” aesthetic, which transmutes categories of time into space, dissimulating the labor-time that lies at the origin of value.[4] There is no better image of this transmutation than a decadent collection, which brings objects created at different historical moments and by different cultures into a single physical space. In his 1889 essay “Pen, Pencil, and Poison,” for example, Wilde draws attention to collections of his subject, Thomas Griffiths Wainewright, for whom “All beautiful things belong to the same age”: “we find the delicate fictile vase of the Greek … and behind it hangs an engraving of the ‘Delphic Sibyl’ of Michelangelo … Here is a bit of Florentine majolica, and here a rude lamp from some Roman tomb” (2007, 108-9). There are books by French poets, antique gems, and works by Turner. These objects are at once material things and evidence of the eclectic tastes of the decadent collector, whose curatorial eye subsumes temporal differences under the evaluative categories of the beautiful, the exceptional, or (like Des Esseintes’s plants) the perverse. It is such conceptual values—and not the monetary value of the objects—that justify their inclusion in the collection. In other words, the value of the collected objects, like that of many financial instruments, is more imaginary than “real.”

    Perhaps the most suggestive connection between decadence and financialization, however, lies in a key nineteenth-century analytical category that Gammelgaard’s attention to linguistic signification unfortunately obscures: decadent style. The major concept under which decadent texts were categorized by contemporary critics, decadent style was (at first) a denigrating name for literary forms that transgressed against classical harmony and simplicity. Bloated, unbalanced, and marked by a superabundance of description and erudition, this style, for critics, mirrored the pathologies of its age. In the single most important characterization of decadence, Paul Bourget describes Charles Baudelaire’s decadent style, in proto-Durkheimian terms, as an index of social of disintegration: the book gives way to the page, the page to the sentence, and the sentence to the word. Friedrich Nietzsche would famously borrow this definition to define Richard Wagner’s decadent style, and along with it the atomizing nature of democratic politics.

    The concept of decadent style was first proposed by the French critic Désiré Nisard in his 1834 study of first-century Latin poetry, Études de moeurs et de critique sur les poètes Latins de la décadence. When Bourget wrote his essay on Baudelaire, he was appropriating a term that was already well-established in French critical discourse. Writing at a moment that Marx, in The Class Struggles in France (1850), associates with the rise of the “finance aristocracy,” Nisard casts the style of poets like Lucan as a figure both for the decline of the Roman Empire and for the economic conditions of his own age. Marx sees the finance aristocracy as a bourgeois equivalent of the Lumpenproletariat—a group made up of former outsiders (primarily Jews, he notes), who improbably ascended to the height of cultural power after the 1830 July Revolution. Nisard sees something similar in ancient Rome. Arriving in the imperial metropole from colonial outposts in Iberia and North Africa, decadent Latin poets like Lucan and Martial subjected hallowed Roman literary traditions to their (bad) provincial taste, casting it in what Nisard terms “the bizarre jargon of the marketplace” (1834, I, 129). Nisard concludes his study with a comparison between decadent Roman poets and “decadent” contemporaries like Victor Hugo, whose poetic innovations he accuses of the same excessive reliance on description and empty erudition as his ancient forbears.

    Read together, Nisard and Marx bring out something about financialized moments that does not often receive its due in critical finance studies: their disruption of the existing class structure. Finance elevates certain outsiders to new positions of privilege, for which they quickly come under attack by rival classes, who decry their “decadent” ways. Decadence in this case is the name given to formerly marginal members of society who have begun making their mark on a conceptual order that treats certain traditions, whether literary or economic, as unquestionably natural. While Nisard saw decadent style as something to be lamented, later decadent writers like Huysmans and Wilde, working in yet another moment of financialization, saw it as a cause for celebration. Des Esseintes’s Latin library, described in chapter three of À rebours, explicitly repudiates the scions of the Golden Age (Cicero, Horace, Virgil) in favor of precisely those “lumpen” outsiders like Lucan that Nisard and other critics of late-Latin style rejected. The sexologist and social reformer Havelock Ellis crystalized just this attitude when he compared Huysmans’s decadent style with the “fantastic mingling of youth and age, of decayed Latinity, of tumultuous youthful Christianity” that characterized African writers like Tertullian and Augustine (1898, 158). For Ellis, early Christianity embodies a condition of uneven and combined cultural development that anticipates the fin-de-siècle belle époque.[5]

    Like many other fin-de-siècle decadent writers—most of them queers, provincials, colonial subjects, and foreigners—Huysmans turns Nisard’s diagnostic category inside out, rendering what is typically a conservative cultural diagnosis potentially radical. The striking disruptions to the class structures that shape the culture of a belle époque may elicit apocalyptic prognostications from traditionalists (of all political stripes), but they also open up new possibilities for the formerly marginalized. This was certainly true of the fin de siècle, which saw the emergence of modern queer identity and the beginnings of anticolonial movements. Despite its common association with philosophical pessimism, the decadent aesthetic speaks to just this sense of new possibility. Condemnations of finance as the “last” or a “late” version of capitalism, which adopt the language of decadence only as a theory of bitter ends, crucially miss its longstanding association with new beginnings. As Neville Morely has put it, decadence “marks the moment when the future begins to come within reach, the point where the present weakens enough to make an alternative conceivable” (2004, 574).

    In “Culture and Finance Capital,” his influential review of The Long Twentieth Century, Fredric Jameson, providing yet another example of the decadent logic of finance, maps Arrighi’s theory of economic cycles onto the familiar stylistic trinity of realism, modernism, and postmodernism. Each step in the stylistic sequence, Jameson argues, is marked by increasing abstraction, reflecting the growing dominance of finance capital. While realism retains a residual commitment to the concrete, modernism frees form and color from their dependence on objects, and postmodernism, as the terminal point in this evolution, detaches artistic styles entirely from their connection to history. Jameson gave no attention to decadent style in his essay, but he should have.[6] More, perhaps, than any modern literary and artistic style, decadence is attuned to historical repetition, and since its earliest adumbration in the 1830s has been understood as the recurrent mark of so-called “decadent” ages—beginning, of course, with the paradigmatic case of imperial Rome. Jameson’s progressive narrative of stylistic change overlooks the cyclical nature of financialization in ways that closer attention to decadent writing would have precluded. The long twentieth century, as I noted above, raised financial markets to unprecedented prominence, but this is only an intensification of economic circumstances that have analogies in other long centuries, something both Arrighi and Braudel insist upon in their longue durée histories of capitalism. Indeed, as theorists from Paine to Lenin to Arrighi himself seem to recognize, if only at the level of imagery, decadence is the house style of financialization. Hence my concluding point: Not only should scholars of decadence follow Gammelgaard’s lead and attend closely to the literature on financialization, but scholars interested in financialization would learn much by attending more closely to the literature on and of decadence.

    Matthew Potolsky is Professor of English at the University of Utah, where he teaches nineteenth-century literature and literary theory. He is the author of three scholarly monographs: Mimesis (2006), The Decadent Republic of Letters: Taste, Politics, and Cosmopolitan Community from Baudelaire to Beardsley (2013), and The National Security Sublime: On the Aesthetics of Government Secrecy (2019). He is also the editor of Classical Studies (2021), the eighth volume of Oxford University Press’ The Collected Works of Walter Pater; and co-editor of Perennial Decay: On the Aesthetics and Politics of Decadence (1999).

    References

    Arrighi, Giovanni. 2010. The Long Twentieth Century: Money, Power and the Origins of Our Times. London: Verso.

    Braudel, Fernand. 1984. Civilization and Capitalism, 15th-18th Century, III: The Perspective of the World, translated by Siân Reynolds. New York: Harper and Row.

    Clover, Joshua. 2011. “Autumn of the System: Poetry and Finance Capital.” Journal of Narrative Theory 41, no. 1: 34-52.

    Dowling, Linda. 1983. Language and Decadence in the Victorian Fin de Siècle. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Ellis, Havelock. 1898. Affirmations. London: Walter Scott.

    Esty, Jed. 2016. “Realism Wars.” Novel: A Forum on Fiction 49, no. 2: 316-42.

    Finch, Laura. 2015. “The Un-real Deal: Financial Fiction, Fictional Finance, and the Financial Crisis.” Journal of American Studies 49, no. 4: 731-53.

    Gagnier, Regenia. 2000. The Insatiability of Human Wants: Economics and Aesthetics in Market Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Gaillard, Françoise. 1980. “A rebours ou l’inversion des signes.” In L’Esprit de la décadence I. Nantes: Minard.

    Gasché, Rodolphe. 1988. “The Falls of History: Huysmans’s A rebours.” Yale French Studies 74: 183–204.

    Huysmans, Joris-Karl. 2003. Against Nature (À Rebours), translated by Robert Baldick. London: Penguin.

    Jameson, Fredric. 1997. “Culture and Finance Capital.” Critical Inquiry 24, no. 1: 246-65.

    Lenin, Vladimir. 1917. Imperialism: The Last Stage of Capitalism. London: Communist Party of Great Britain.

    Marx, Karl. 1960. The Class Struggles in France, 1848-1850. Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House.

    Marx, Karl. 1981. Capital, Vol. 3, translated by David Fernbach. London: Penguin.

    Montesquieu, Charles de Secondat. 1951. Cahiers (1716-1755), edited by Bernard Grasset. Paris: Grasset.

    Morely, Neville. 2004. “Decadence as a Theory of History.” New Literary History 35, no. 4: 573-85.

    Nisard, Désiré. 1834. Études de moeurs et de critique sur les poètes Latins de la décadence. 3 vols. Brussels: Louis Hauman.

    Sewell, William H. 2012. “Economic Crises and the Shape of Modern History.” Public Culture 24, no. 2: 303-27.

    Spackman, Barbara. 1999. “Interversions.” In Perennial Decay: On the Aesthetics and Politics of Decadence, edited by Liz Constable, Dennis Denisoff, and Matthew Potolsky, pp. 35-49. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Wilde, Oscar. 2007. The Complete Works of Oscar Wilde, IV: Criticism, edited by Josephine M. Guy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    [1] Extending her claim, we might also place À rebours in the company of more recent finance-era classics like Tom Wolfe’s The Bonfire of the Vanities (1987) and Bret Easton Ellis’s American Psycho (1991), both of which recall fin-de-siècle forbears.

    [2] Gammelgaard treads overfamiliar terrain here. The comparison of Jevons and Saussure recapitulates the insights of the New Economic Criticism; Gagnier (2000) explores the connection between fin-de-siècle writing and the marginal revolution; Dowling (1983) finds a key to decadent aesthetics in the history of linguistics. Other scholars—notably Gaillard (1980), Gasché (1988), and Spackman (1999)—explore the unusual workings of language and signification in Huysmans’s novel.

    [3] On the extent to which economic crises function as historical events, see Sewell.

    [4] Clover associates the term with W.B. Yeats, a writer deeply influenced by 1890s poetry, but finds his chief examples of autumnal style in postmodern figures like Pynchon and Ashbury.

    [5] In his 1895 introduction to The Class Struggles in France, Friedrich Engels compares contemporary socialists to early Christians: “The Emperor Diocletian could no longer quietly look on while order, obedience and discipline in his army were being undermined…He promulgated an anti-Socialist—beg pardon, I meant to say anti-Christian—law” (1960, 41). The origin for this analogy is probably Ernest Renan, but it was clearly popular at the fin de siècle. It is worth asking, in this regard, whether Leon Trotsky’s theory of uneven and combined development might not also have a decadent lineage. Trotsky’s literary criticism from the 1920s demonstrates an extensive knowledge (mostly critical) of fin-de-siècle literary forms, and his familiarity with such works might well have inflected his discussion of the peculiarities of Russian development in The History of the Russian Revolution (1930). He offers there a strikingly “decadent” theory of economic development.

    [6] Jameson does make a surprising reference to Wilde in “Culture and Finance Capital.” Noting that Marxist critics have tended to avoid the exploring the stylistic implications of modes of production because it requires too many mediations, he writes that this avoidance is “no doubt in the spirit in which Oscar Wilde complained that socialism required too many evenings” (1997, 253). Gammelgaard’s account of decadence, it is worth noting, would, in Jameson’s sequence, be most akin to realism. For an effort to think cyclically about the resonances of fin-de-siècle forms, specifically about their opposition to realism, see Esty (2016).

  • Signe Leth Gammelgaard–Flowers Without Meaning: Literary Decadence as Finance Aesthetics

    Signe Leth Gammelgaard–Flowers Without Meaning: Literary Decadence as Finance Aesthetics

    This article was published as part of the b2o review‘s “Finance and Fiction” dossier. The dossier includes a response to this article by Matthew Potolsky. 

    Signe Leth Gammelgaard–Flowers Without Meaning: Literary Decadence as Finance Aesthetics

    In chapter eight of Joris-Karl Huysmans’s À rebours, the protagonist Jean Des Esseintes muses on his collection of hothouse flowers. The novel is one of the most prominent examples of the literary decadence of the late nineteenth century and such artificially cultivated flowers (as well as the hothouse itself) are a recurrent motif in decadent literature. In his “Préface écrit vingt ans après le roman” Huysmans himself describes the flowers of À rebours as “aphonic” or “mute” (atteinte d’alabie, muette). This imagery of organic flowers, cultivated to mimic artificial flowers as the text explains, conjures up a rather striking scene which epitomizes the decadent aesthetic. This aesthetic can be understood, I want to propose, in light of contemporaneous economic developments, specifically the intensification of the impact of finance – as portrayed in other literary works from the same period, for instance the classic stock-exchange novels of Émile Zola’s L’Argent or Anthony Trollope’s The Way We Live Now.

    In what follows, I use Giovanni Arrighi’s model of financial expansion as a recurrent phenomenon throughout the history of capitalism. The final decades of the nineteenth century were one period of such expansion, where a major part of the money capital became invested rather in financial instruments and assets than in material production. The late nineteenth century, then, in some ways productively mirrors our current period of financialization which began in the 1970s, even if it is not understood as the same period of financial expansion in Arrighi’s framework (Arrighi 2010, 6–7). The significant rise in the impact of finance in the latter half of the nineteenth century occurred especially in the imperial centers of France and Britain. This rise has been portrayed in various ways in the literature of the period, and particularly within the framework of the realist novel, a subject of numerous studies in the past decades. In new economic criticism, the Victorian period specifically has been the focus of several important works, like Mary Poovey’s Genres of the Credit Economy and Catherine Gallagher’s The Body Economic. However, less attention has been paid to the literary fin de siècle, the stylistic developments of decadence and aestheticism.

    In this article, I propose to outline some key parallels between the aesthetic traits of these movements and the concurrent development in the economic system, in particular the steady rise of financial instruments, trades, and structures. I start by analyzing the core decadent aesthetics traits as opposed to earlier realist aesthetics, and then contextualize these by their relationship to the development of Ferdinand de Saussure’s structural linguistics. I then show how Saussure’s linguistics parallel another theoretical shift, namely the marginal revolution in economic theory. Finally, I will examine how these three shifts respond to larger economic trends in the period; specifically, the switch from an emphasis on material production to an emphasis on financial investment and instruments.

    The parallels between linguistic and economic systems have been illuminated before. My central point in this article is that the decadent aesthetics, specifically, render a representational shift in a way that generates an existential and perceptive view on this period and on its changes in both economics and language; namely a loss of meaning. It also presents a strategy of response to such a situation in the form of a renegotiation of the relationship between signs and material reality.

    The mute flowers of decadence

    Huysmans’s À rebours is a peculiar novel. While it has often been described as plotless,[1] the frame of the narrative in fact provides a simple storyline and the epitome of a decadent one at that. As the last scion of an old, degenerated family, Jean Des Esseintes delves into various extreme and debauched lifestyles before he, weary with the depraved Paris life, retreats to a house he buys outside the city, in Fontenay. The majority of the book details his decorating of this house and his aesthetic choices and sensory experiences with various stimulants: art, literature, colors, interior design, gemstones, flowers, music, perfumes, culinary delights. Finally, however, his body is worn out by his excessive enjoyment, and he is urged by his doctors to return to a normal life and “to enjoy himself, in short, like other people” (Huysmans 2009a, 173).

    The flower chapter outlines very clearly how these aesthetic experiences work. It opens by stating that, though Des Esseintes has “always adored flowers” he is now only interested in one kind: the hothouse flowers. The passage outlines this development: after his love of real flowers, he had, in his previous life in Paris and in line with his “natural inclination towards artifice,” amassed a large collection of artificial flowers “faithfully imitated thanks to the miracles of gums and threads, percalines and taffetas, papers and velvet” (Huysmans 2009a, 72–73). However, with his move to Fontenay, a new phase emerges and the narrator comments regarding the artificial flowers: “He had long been fascinated by this wonderful art-form; but now he dreamt of planning a different kind of flora. After having artificial flowers that imitated real ones, he now wanted real flowers that mimicked artificial ones” (Huysmans 2009a, 73). As such, the hothouse blooms become an almost parodical expression of a crisis of representation, with plants cultivated artificially in “the carefully measured warmth of stoves” (Huysmans 2009a, 72), to look like fake ones, that in turn look like real ones.

    Des Esseintes tours the horticulturalists of the area of Fontenay and orders a collection of plants. When they arrive, the narrative describes how some “were extraordinary, pinkish in colour, like the Virginal which looked like it had been made out of oilcloth or court plaster; some were entirely white, like the Albany, which could have been cut from the transparent pleura of an ox,” some “mimicked zinc, parodying pieces of punched metal that had been dyed Emperor green and stained with drops of oil-paint and splashes of red and white lead” (Huysmans 2009a, 73–74). As such, the sensory impression of the flowers takes center stage: how they look and what they look like. Conversely, the narrative does not in any way refer to the symbolic language of flowers, that is, metaphoric, traditional or symbolic meanings of love, hope or virtue.

    This point is at the center of both Suzanne Braswell’s and Robert Ziegler’s analysis of the hothouse flowers of À rebours. Ziegler underscores, by reference to Huysmans’s own preface from twenty years later and thus written after his conversion to Catholicism, precisely the muteness of the flowers (Ziegler 2015, 51–52). In this Préface écrit vingt ans après le roman,” Huysmans notes:

    It would have been difficult, in that novel, to endow an aphonic flower, a mute flower, with speech, for the symbolic language of plants died with the Middle Ages and the exotic flora dear to Des Esseintes were not known to the allegorists of that age. (Huysmans 2009b, 190)

    Ziegler’s analysis portrays this muteness through comparison to Huysmans’s later work, in particular the novel La Cathédrale, where the flowers and plants have become re-endowed with meaning through the work of religion, through Huysmans’s conversion. However, as the quotation shows, the mute flowers adhere to a modern condition, albeit the modernity that began already with the end of the Middle Ages.

    Braswell’s analysis takes a broader view on this modernity and traces discourses on the symbolic language-of-flowers. Her reading stresses specific changes in these discourses precisely towards the end of the nineteenth century and she argues that, while Stéphane Mallarmé’s work nuances and elaborates the earlier traditions, the flowers in À rebours in turn “attack the tradition and parody its discourses, particularly those promoting the healthful and chaste aspects of horticulture” (Braswell 2013, 76, 83). The point that emerges is that these elaborate, exotic, and artificially cultivated plants have become such a perverse manifestation that they no longer signify; rather, they look like various forms of dying or diseased flesh, rendering distinct “necrotic dimensions” as Braswell terms it (Braswell 2013, 83). In the novel, this is seen in the passage on the next round of flowers to arrive:

    they simulated the appearance of fake skin scored by artificial veins; and the majority, as though eaten away by syphilis and leprosy, exhibited livid flesh marbled with roseola and damasked with dartres; others were the bright pink of scars that are healing, or the browning tint of scabs in the process of forming; others were blistering from cautery or puffing up from burns (Huysmans 2009a, 74).

    This imagery of decaying organisms, diseased tissue and putrefying flesh, however, links the floral passages to linguistic developments as they are described both in À rebours and in the movement of decadence more generally. In a previous chapter Des Esseintes meditates on his literary preferences, specifically among the Latin authors of the Roman decadence. Here, the narrator explains that:

    Des Esseintes’s interest in the Latin language remained undiminished, now that it hung like a completely rotted corpse, its limbs falling off, dripping with pus, and preserving, in the total corruption of its body, barely a few firm parts, which the Christians took away to steep in the brine of their new idiom. (Huysmans 2009a, 31)

    The advent of Christianity is given a key role in the development where the language of the Pagan Rome “decomposed like venison,” in fact “falling apart at the same time as the civilization of the Ancient World crumbled into dust, at the same time as the Empires, rotted by the putrefaction of the centuries, collapsed under the onslaught of the Barbarians” (Huysmans 2009a, 28).

    The decadence of a civilization is thus matched by the decadence of its linguistic forms – forms that are in turn described in the same language as the appearance of the mute flowers, the flowers that have lost their metaphorical meanings. However, the idea of a decomposing organism of language is not specific to Huysmans. Indeed, in his Decadence and the Making of Modernism, David Weir comments on an earlier example of decadent criticism, namely Theophile Gautier’s essay on Baudelaire from 1868 (Weir 1995, 88–89). In this essay, Gautier, similar to Des Esseintes’s reflections, connect the decadent Latin literature to the literature of his own time. Moreover, he examines Baudelaire’s relationship to the “masters of the past,” in whom he cannot find an adequate model for his own period, since these masters had been born “when the world was young,” and “when as yet nothing had been expressed” (Gautier 1908, 38). Gautier writes further:

    The great commonplaces that form the main stock of human thought were then in their first flush, and sufficed for simple geniuses addressing a people yet childish. But by dint of being repeated, these general poetic themes had become worn, like coins that have been too long in circulation and have lost their sharpness of outline; besides, life has become more complex, contains more notions and ideas, and is no longer sufficiently reproduced in artificial compositions inspired by the spirit of another age. (Gautier 1908, 38)

    The metaphor of the worn-out coin instantly establishes a parallel between the representational system of money, and that of language. In the original French the wording is “perdent leur empreinte” rather than “lost their sharpness of outline”, so the image underscores how the coins have gradually lost their imprint, their stated value, effecting a mismatch between the form and content of the coin: its “meaning” has been skewed. The passage thus describes a shift in representation, and Gautier links this shift to a decadent Zeitgeist.

    With recourse to Roland Barthes’s “L’Effet de réel,” this gap between form and content can be inscribed in a larger narrative. While Barthes’s short essay revolves mainly around his conception of the reality effect, towards the end of the text he speculates on a more general meaning of this particular effect. He argues that realism, conceived around the notion of this reality effect, is in fact a forerunner to the problematized representation of his own time, described in Barthes’s words as a “disintegration of the sign – which seems indeed to be modernity’s grand affair” (Barthes 2006, 234). Furthermore, he states, “the goal today is to empty the sign and infinitely to postpone its object so as to challenge, in a radical fashion, the age-old aesthetic of ‘representation’” (Barthes 2006, 234).

    Barthes describes the concept of the reality effect, key to his understanding of realism, in a way that aligns with the decadent aesthetic seen in Huysmans’s flowers, namely that of a mute, unsignifying materiality. The reality effect thus invokes the material world not to signify anything specifically in a narrative context but merely to denote the reality of the stated utterance. Barthes writes:

    Semiotically, the “concrete detail” is constituted by the direct collusion of a referent and a signifier; the signified is expelled from the sign, and with it, of course, the possibility of developing a form of the signified, i.e., narrative structure itself. […] in other words, the very absence of the signified, to the advantage of the referent alone, becomes the very signifier of realism: the reality effect is produced, the basis of that unavowed verisimilitude which forms the aesthetic of all the standard works of modernity. (Barthes 2006, 234)

    What Barthes describes here is essentially a “flat” material world, a disenchanted and meaningless observation of the purely material properties. However, Barthes’s analysis identifies this aesthetic through the conception of the “absence of the signified.” To understand this in more depth, I now turn to Ferdinand de Saussure’s original conception of the dual sign consisting of signifier and signified.

    Saussure’s structuralism and the disintegration of the sign

    Saussure’s most famous work is presented in the Cours de linguistique générale, a work based on a series of lectures given by him between 1906 and 1911 and compiled from notes by Charles Bally and Albert Sechehaye. Though Saussure never published this work himself, the course has had a large significance for various fields outside of linguistics and, according to letters and notes that have since been found, Saussure started thinking about issues in general linguistics already in the final decades of the nineteenth century – in other words, contemporary to the decadent movement (Culler 1976, 15). In fact, economics seems to have been an inspiration for the ways in which Saussure wanted to redefine linguistics, and in the Cours he refers to the content of the linguistic sign as its “value,” but only insofar as the signified, the concept or meaning of a sign, has a value exactly because it is part of a system of language and compared to other values and signs (Saussure 2011, 114–17).

    The Saussurian innovation resides largely in the dual nature of the sign: it consists of two parts, namely signifier and signified. According to Saussure, language is not made up of connections between signs and the material world but is rather a system of signs comprised by signifiers and signifieds. The signifier is the sound-image (the image of sound exists even if it is not pronounced) and the signified is the mental concept, meaning what we think of when we hear the sound-image. The relation between these two parts of the sign is arbitrary; though there are some onomatopoetic words, in general the relation between a specific word and its mental concept is random. Saussure refers specifically to the signified as the “meaning” or “content” of the sign, which then has value in a system (Saussure 2011, 65–78, 114–17). As such, the signified also holds the mediating function of language, the process by which we interpret arbitrary signifiers into meaningful content which we can then draw upon in our interaction with the physical world. When the reality effect in the decadent aesthetics is conceived as a “direct collusion” between referent and signifier, a lack of a proper signified, it signals a loss of narrative meaning.

    However, for Saussure this understanding also enables a new conception of linguistics itself. Language can be understood as a structure or system in which each sign has meaning only in relation to other, different signs. The material world – termed “the referent” in semiotics ­– lies beyond the scope of linguistics according to Saussure, as it is the structure of language that should be studied in this discipline. Hence, structural linguistics brackets the idea of an underlying material reality: Linguistics should thus not be concerned with the connection between referent and signified, or for that matter between referent and signifier, but should only study linguistics as a differential relationship between signs. It is the difference of one word from that of another that gives it its meaning, not its connection to any actual thing.

    Barthes’s analysis shows a very explicit use of Saussure’s dual sign: the duality of signifier and signified enables an analytical description of what is happening when representation becomes problematic, when the materiality becomes mute and meaningless. The conception that the “form of the signified” is the narrative structure itself is, moreover, interesting in the sense that, while Barthes’s examples in the essay refers to realist works that do have a storyline or plot, À rebours is often described as a novel without a plot. While it is a feature of realism (and only realism) in Barthes, I argue that the reality effect is a core component of the estrangement of the mute flowers in À rebours. In Huysmans’s novel (and in decadence more generally) the reality effect becomes not only a specific aesthetic strategy but the whole point of the narrative: it is central to the loss of meaning that drives the novel.

    Following the work of scholars like Mary Poovey and Jean-Joseph Goux, I would now like to contextualize this shift from the meaningful narrative of realism to a decadence describing a loss of meaning beyond Saussure’s contemporaneous structural linguistics, namely in a parallel to the economic sphere (which is present in Saussure’s theory, as I have already shown).

    The liquid values of marginal utility

    Around 1870, the field of political economy spawned a significant new set of ideas that, similar to the decadent literature, augurs a new relationship between material reality and language or signs, in this case the language of values and economics. Independently of each other, three theorists in three different countries simultaneously developed theories based on the notion of marginal utility: W. Stanley Jevons in England, Léon Walras in Switzerland, and Carl Menger in Austria. The basic tenet of these theories is the idea that the value of anything can be determined by the thing’s marginal utility, that is, the utility of the “last available item” of a specific commodity. The amount and availability of something thus becomes the central parameter, because its utility will decrease with the amount available. Thus, when there is plenty of water, even though it is necessary for survival, its value will be low. On the other hand, when water is a scarce resource, its value will be incredibly high. The value of a commodity is thus expressed by the commodity’s exchange value, its price in a market (Jevons 1999, 143). The notion of value in this way becomes tied to the concept of scarcity.

    With the marginalist perspective the value of something thereby shifts away from the earlier focus on the cost it takes to produce it, and towards the intensity of the desire that it can create – essentially the shift goes away from production and towards consumption, and this has consequences for the relationship between prices – the monetary sign – and material world of commodities. To understand precisely what the shift in economic theory entails and how it parallels decadent aesthetics and structural linguistics, a brief review of Marx’s notion of value is useful.

    While the earlier field of political economy spearheaded by Adam Smith, David Ricardo, Thomas Robert Malthus, and Karl Marx had many disagreements, the prior theories all revolved around the concept of a labor theory of value. Marx divided the concept of value into three separate notions, namely “use value”, “exchange value”, and “value” itself (Marx and Engels 1996, 45–51). The latter one is at the core of his theory of capitalism as it elucidates how the exchange between capitalist and worker takes place. Capitalism, according to Marx, is the specific situation where the worker has nothing to sell but his labor power, and where the capitalist, conversely, holds the means of production including the necessary capital to establish a production of some commodity. Labor power is also a commodity and it is the only commodity a worker can sell. Contrary to other commodities, however, labor has the specific feature that it can produce more value than it takes to reproduce it – basically, a laborer can work more and produce more than what is required for her own reproduction and survival. This “more” is what Marx defines as surplus value, and the relationship between capitalist and worker is defined by the fact that the surplus value falls to the capitalist. While the basic level of reproduction is historically and geographically variable, the central mechanism remains the same, even if the worker is granted higher wages for her own reproduction (Marx 2016, 885).

    However, the way Marx links the concept of labor time to value is central, because it shows how the whole economic system is linked to the material needs of a given society, and thereby anchors the theory in material reality. For labor to be the basic universal equivalent, namely the thing that enables the exchange of two qualitatively different commodities, Marx introduces the concept of abstract labor time. This concept expresses the amount of labor time necessary for a given society to uphold its current state and it is thus an abstract concept, not possible to measure in any exact way. The value of a given commodity is the labor time it takes on average to produce it, expressed as a fraction of the total socially necessary labor time of a society. Thus, the value of a specific commodity is not larger if it is produced by a slow worker than a similar one produced by a fast worker (Marx and Engels 1996, 48–49). As such the concept of abstract labor time both lodges the labor theory of value in a concrete material reality (namely the necessary amount of labor to sustain a society) and gives a commodity an underlying value described as a part of this necessary labor. It is this relationship to reality that changes with the new economics, and that change can in turn be related to the shift from realist narrative language to decadent mute description.

    According to Marx the exchange value will over time stabilize around the actual value of something. Indeed, he states in volume one of Capital that “the labour time socially necessary for their production forcibly asserts itself like an over-riding law of Nature” (Marx and Engels 1996, 86). Thus, while exchange values (that is, the prices) does figure into Marx’s theoretical edifice, they function mainly as expressions of the underlying value that has a relationship to societal value as a whole – and these expressions can be more or less representative or accurate (Marx 2016, 460). In the marginal utility theory, this calculation of labor time vanishes and production cost is assigned a different role, namely as a component of a cost-benefit analysis on the part of the producer. In marginal utility theory, also called neoclassical economics, value expresses only intensities of desire – the desire for the pleasure of consuming something versus the pain of acquiring it (the labor necessary for obtaining it), and relative to other things that can be acquired for the same amount of “pain.” These calculations of pleasure and pain then meet up with the similar calculations of other actors in a marketplace, and generates a price: the desire of the buyer for consumption meets the “pain” that the producer has put into creating it and therefore needs compensation for. The price becomes an exact expression of value, because value is no longer defined as some underlying quality, but only as the price that a good can obtain in a marketplace (Gallagher 2008, 126–27).

    Jean-Joseph Goux expands on this point and claims:

    Any questioning of “value” beyond a state of equilibrium momentarily offered by a market, or auction, of pure competition becomes a futile, useless, metaphysical and unscientific pursuit. For Walras, Karl Marx, like Adam Smith, remains a metaphysician; both Marx and Smith seek a unique and enduring principle that would fix value, the universal law regulating the exchange of products, which they find in the time of labour. (Goux 1997, 163)

    I have dwelled at some length on this precise difference because the central shift regards a conception of labor and of the material reality to which prices refer. Thus, when we saw in the decadent literature a changed relationship between the referent and the signifier, expressed as a loss of the meaning – a loss of the signified – here we have a system of thought that is no longer interested in the relationship between signified and referent. Signs refer only to other signs in the system. As Goux portrays it, there is no longer any fixed point to which value refers, no concrete reality. Value only expresses wants, and these wants fluctuate according to scarcity (real or artificial), usefulness and, last but not least, the ability of something to create desire. Goux describes this conception of value as the “stock-exchange paradigm” as it fits with the way the stock exchange works. For Goux, this is not merely a change in economic theory, but a development that describes modernity as such, and like Barthes’s idea of “modernity’s grand affair,” it concerns a specific change in the way that signs work (Goux 1997).

    However, while Saussure’s linguistics and marginalist economics both bracket the relationship of signs to the material world, the decadent aesthetics present a very precise way that the loss of a connection between societal values and material reality can take on an existential dimension and be perceived as a loss of meaning tout court. A few decades after Gautier’s aforementioned text, in 1881, a different critic of decadence, namely Paul Bourget, examines the relationships between linguistic and societal meaning through the example of Baudelaire in relation to decadence. The parallel Bourget sees between these two registers is through the image of the organism. A decadent society, he holds, is characterized by a state of affairs where the individual units, the smaller cells and lesser organisms, become independent and no longer work by subordinating their energy to the total organism. Same principle for language, he claims:

    The very same rule governs the development and the decadence of another organism, language. A decadent style is one in which the unity of the book falls apart, replaced by the independence of the page, where the page decomposes to make way for the independence of the sentence, and the sentence makes way for the word. There are innumerable examples in current literature to corroborate this hypothesis and justify this analogy (Bourget 2009, 98).

    This quotation, often cited and used as definition for the decadent style, describes fragmentation and lack of any conception of totality or coherent whole, and the text describes this “anarchy” as a state of decline of both the organism of society and that of language. With the parallels between the new economic thinking and the new linguistic theory of the final decades of the century, falling apart and lack of unity of the decadent aesthetics can be understood in relation to shifts in the economic sphere. However, while the marginalist theory shows a system that becomes unlinked to the material necessities of a given society’s reproduction, it does not explain what happened in the actual economy of the period and how that relates to literary expression. To explain this link, and why it results in an aesthetics of fragmentation and disunity, Mary Poovey’s work is more instructive than Goux’.

    In Genres of the Credit Economy (2008), Poovey expounds on the parallels between money, economics, language, and literature in a historically grounded perspective, reading two centuries of British literary and economic history in conjunction. By doing so, Genres makes a key point about the historical dynamic between these two systems. In Poovey’s account, they do not only display parallel features, they also actively influence one another. Concerning specifically what Poovey terms the “problematic of representation” – that is, “the gap that separates the sign from its referent or ground (of value or meaning), whether the gap takes the form of deferral, substitution, approximation, or obscurity” (Poovey 2008, 5) – she states:

    Unlike most Literary critics, however, I do not present the problematic of representation as a property of all systems of representation. Instead, I argue that representation becomes problematic—it presents problems that are both social and epistemological—only at certain times and under conditions that are historically and socially specific. A system of representation is experienced as problematic only when it ceases to work—that is, when something in the social context calls attention to the deferral or obfuscation of its authenticating ground. (Poovey 2008, 5–6)

    The thing in the social context that can cause this awareness is mainly economic events, for instance crises, crashes, bubbles, and mania. Thus, Poovey foregrounds the notion that the representational function is historically variable, at the same time as she stresses the connection between linguistic and monetary systems. While Poovey does not operate with the Saussurian concepts of signifier and signified but rather conflates the notions of signified and referent in the above passage, it is clear that her point relates to the problem of materiality and meaning. Like the shifts related to decadent aesthetics, Saussure’s linguistics, and Goux’s reading of marginal utility theory, the sign begins to work differently. Huysmans’s novel shows, indeed, how such crises of representation can be interpreted through an aesthetics of the lost signified, in Barthes’ words the “direct collusion of a referent and a signifier.”

    À rebours thus portrays a situation in which its protagonist experiences a ‘mute referent’ in place of a narrative signified for the flowers. However, for the reader of the novel the words themselves naturally still have a meaning – they still have a signified. Telling the story of a lost signified for the character – the story of a mute and meaningless materiality – thus becomes the narrative signified for the reader: the text becomes a meaningful expression about the loss of meaning in both a linguistic and an existential sense. Furthermore, while these flowers are no longer endowed with metaphorical meaning, they still look like something, namely decaying bodies, an image which is also used to describe the linguistic disintegration of representation in both Huysmans and elsewhere. In so far as these descriptions of flowers still do signify, they signify on the one hand the mute referent in a Barthesian sense, and on the other connote an imagery of disintegrating organisms. In both cases, they signal a shift in representation, a shift in the mediating function of the signified. With Poovey’s notion of economic events as a trigger for such representational issues in mind, I will now turn to the actual economic changes of the period.

    The late nineteenth century crisis

    The final decades of the nineteenth century saw an economic situation in the old European empires that in some central ways matches that of the US today: repeated crashes and volatile economy, a huge increase in the impact of the financial sector, staggering growth and a cut-throat price competition. In terms of imperial affairs, this period is known for the “scramble for Africa,” the intense round of colonization of African territories which increased the European control from 10 percent to 90 percent over two decades. Literary scholars and historians alike have described the massive boom in financial instruments and stock-companies, accompanied both by new legislation and the pressure for better information through a reliable, critical press (Kornbluh 2014, 1–2; Henry and Schmitt 2009; Poovey 2002, 17–18; 2008, 274; Taylor 2014). According to Giovanni Arrighi’s The Long Twentieth Century, the year 1870 augurs the financial phase of the period of capitalist development that he terms the British cycle, and this financial phase followed an initial phase of material expansion (characterized by increased production, colonial ventures and intensification of trade). The financial phase of this period was characterized by capital agencies withdrawing from investment in material production and trades, and concentrating instead on banking, money trades and finance, and such change indicates the decline of a period of capitalist development in Arrighi’s model. Drawing on the work of Fernand Braudel, Arrighi states that “financial expansions are taken to be symptomatic of a situation in which the investment of money in the expansion of trade and production no longer serves the purpose of increasing the cash flow to the capitalist stratum as effectively as pure financial deals can” (Arrighi 2010, 9). The late nineteenth century financialization thus spelled the end of the British (and French) cycle while the United States became the new power center, breeding new material growth.

    The onset of literary decadence, the shift towards the financial phase, the invention of a new conception of economic value and modeling, and the birth of a new linguistic theory thus all center around these decades and the 1870s specifically. At the same time, these four events all display issues in the functioning of the signified: the role of the signified as mediator to the referent is challenged by the way that the referent appears irrelevant in marginalism and in structural linguistics, and the role of the signified is in turn replaced by images of a mute material referent in the later forms of realism and in the movement of decadence especially. However, I have yet to show the role of the signified in financialization. In order to do so I will turn once more to Marx’s writings.

    In the Economic Manuscript of 1864–1865 (his only full draft for volume III of Capital), Marx analyses the dynamics of loan capital and interest and describes the basic mechanism through the model of capitalist production and surplus value. Where the typical cycle for capitalist production is expressed by the formula M–C­­­–M’, where an amount of money (M) is used to produce commodities (C), which can then be sold for a larger amount of money (M’ = the original amount + the surplus value), the expression of loan capital (that is, investments) becomes M–M’ to the lender-capitalist, where the surplus money derives from the interest paid on the loan. What disappears from the formula, then, is precisely the materiality of the commodity and, in Marx’s understanding also therefore the embodied abstract labor power required to produce said commodity. Instead, the formula expresses an amount of money that appears to be growing by itself over time. In chapter 5, part 1, he discusses the expression that the rate of interest is the “price of money,” calling this price a “purely abstract form, completely lacking in content” (“rein abstrakte und inhaltslose Form”) (Marx 2016, 458; Marx, Engels, and Müller 1992, 4:426). What is meant by this lack of content is outlined through a comparison to the prices of regular commodities governed by the following rule:

    If supply and demand coincide, the market price of the commodity corresponds to its price of production, i.e., its price is then governed by the inner laws of capitalist production, independently of competition, since fluctuations in supply and demand explain nothing but divergences between market prices and prices of production (Marx 2016, 460).

    Marx goes on to emphasize, then, that no such divergences exist for the “price” of capital (that is, the interest) as there simply “is no natural rate of interest. What is called the natural rate of interest means rather the rate established by free competition” (Marx 2016, 460). Marx thus outlines that the interest, the price of capital, is equal to what came to be understood as value by the marginalists, a value determined by competition and with no ties to the amount of labor needed to reproduce a given society. It is value in the sense that Goux terms the stock-exchange paradigm, and what is omitted from this conception is the labor of production, embodied in commodities, and which in Marx’s schema can be seen as the signified of money. I therefore suggest that these shifts–the shift of aesthetics, the shift of linguistics, the shift of economic theory–are in turn related to the larger shift from a society based on the production and commerce of commodities produced by labor power, to the commerce of various forms of financial products. Arrighi stresses this point of going from Marx’s theoretical model to a conception of historical phases and explains:

    Marx’s general formula of capital (MCM’) can therefore be interpreted as depicting not just the logic of individual capitalist investments, but also a recurrent pattern of historical capitalism as world system. The central aspect of this pattern is the alternation of epochs of material expansion (MC phases of capital accumulation) with phases of financial rebirth and expansion (CM’ phases). In phases of material expansion money capital “sets in motion” an increasing mass of commodities (including commoditized labor-power and gifts of nature); and in phases of financial expansion an increasing mass of money capital “sets itself free” from its commodity form, and accumulation proceeds through financial deals (as in Marx’s abridged formula MM’). Together, the two epochs or phases constitute a full systemic cycle of accumulation (MCM’). (Arrighi 2010, 6)

    This historical shift might perhaps also be used to understand why the theoretical framework of Capital, with its pinnacle of the labor theory of value, was not, after the 1870s, the most adequate framework to explain market dynamics, because, in a phase dominated by finance capital, the marginal utility theory more adequately explains how value is conceived since the economy is no longer organized mainly around material production. However, invoking the larger framework of the world systems as Arrighi does, reinscribes the finance capitalist systems as phases in a larger dynamic. And within this dynamic, what happens in phases of financial expansion, is that the signified of money (commodities and labor), disappears from view. We then get two new theories that explain how sign systems begin to work, and we get a decadent aesthetics that tries to renegotiate a material world that the theories are no longer concerned with.

    The decadent literature, then, does not simply decouple language from the material realm like the structural linguistics or marginalist economics, but presents, rather, a different kind of connection to it. Most decadent works place a premium on the concept of sensory and sensual enjoyment, epitomized in Des Esseintes’s practices as an aesthete. While on the one hand, this enjoyment undeniably parodies consumption by taking it to the utter extreme, it can also be interpreted as an attempt to reconnect with the material world, to reinvent “meaning” as “sense” in a situation that is no longer mediated by the previous social functioning of the signified. The material world appears meaningless but at the same time menacing, strange, and incomprehensible, accessible only by the sheer sensory properties it invokes. And thus, these properties must be examined, dealt with, experienced, in “a new Hedonism” as it is termed in Oscar Wilde’s The picture of Dorian Gray (Wilde 2006, 22). The success of this “solution” however, is questionable, as most of the decadent works end on a somber note. Thus, when Des Esseintes ponders his return to normal society the book ends with his prayer to a divinity he fails to believe in: “Lord, take pity on the Christian who doubts, on the unbeliever who longs to believe, on the galley-slave of life who is setting sail alone, at night, under a sky no longer lit by the consoling beacons of the ancient hope” (Huysmans 2009a, 181).

    Conclusion

    While previous research has in various ways established parallels between language and money or economics, I have focused on decadent aesthetics because they show a very precise way that large economic changes in society can impact the ways in which we perceive the social and material world. They suggest, in particular, one way in which the subject can react to a phase of financial intensification: by a rather fetishistic relationship to materiality. In the decadent aesthetic, the properties of things in the material world become defining for our experience of them, rather than their social meaning, function, or usefulness. In decadent novels, this is also linked with excessive consumption, even hedonism. As there can no longer be found any social meaning, the only grounding principle for the subject is the sensory experience of the material world. This world, however, lacks any substantive ordering principle and becomes an excess of impressions.

    By establishing the structural parallel between literary decadence and the economic and financial developments of the period, I am also suggesting that the free-floating, differential values of the Saussurian linguistics, and of the neoclassical economics, are responses to the same global developments in the mode of production. The final point I want to emphasize is that decadent literature’s way of responding to the changes I have discussed, differs from the theoretical responses in linguistics and economics by insisting on the relevance of sensory experience and materiality. In a sense, À rebours is trying to figure out what to do with a materiality that can no longer really be understood through the models we know, and it describes the loss of tethering that this social fragmentation results in. The protagonist becomes, quite literally, unhinged from a topsy-turvy world in which meaning remains at large.

    Signe Leth Gammelgaard is a postdoc in comparative literature at Lund University. Her research focuses on the intersection of literary and economic history.

    References

    Arrighi, Giovanni. 2010. The Long Twentieth Century: Money, Power, and the Origins of Our Times. 2nd ed. London; New York: Verso.

    Barthes, Roland. 2006. “The Reality Effect.” In The Novel: An Anthology of Criticism and Theory, 1900-2000, edited by Dorothy J. Hale, 229–34. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

    Bourget, Paul. 2009. “The Example of Baudelaire.” Translated by Nancy O’Connor. New England Review (1990-) 30 (2): 90–104.

    Braswell, Suzanne. 2013. “Mallarmé, Huysmans, and the Poetics of Hothouse Blooms.” French Forum 38 (1/2): 69–87.

    Culler, Jonathan. 1976. Saussure. Fontana Modern Masters. London: Harvester Press.

    Gallagher, Catherine. 2008. The Body Economic, Life, Death, and Sensation in Political Economy and the Victorian Novel. Princeton University Press.

    Gammelgaard, Signe Leth. 2020. “Indebted Bodies: Debt and Decadence in the Nineteenth-Century Novel.” PhD dissertation. Gothenburg: University of Gothenburg.

    Gautier, Theophile. 1908. The Works of Theophile Gautier, Vol. 23, Art and Criticism: The Magic Hat. George D. Sproul. http://archive.org/details/worksoftheophile028595mbp.

    Goux, Jean-Joseph. 1997. “Values and Speculations: The Stock Exchange Paradigm.” Cultural Values 1 (2): 159–77. https://doi.org/10.1080/14797589709367142.

    Henry, Nancy, and Cannon Schmitt, eds. 2009. Victorian Investments: New Perspectives on Finance and Culture. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Huysmans, J.-K. 2009a. Against Nature. Translated by Margaret Mauldon. Oxford World’s Classics. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press.

    ———. 2009b. “Appendix: Preface ‘Written Twenty Years after the Novel.’” In Against Nature, by J.-K. Huysmans, translated by Margaret Mauldon, 183–97. Oxford World’s Classics. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press.

    Jevons, William Stanley. 1999. “Brief Account of a General Mathematical Theory of Political Economy.” In Sources: Notable Selections in Economics, edited by Belay Seyoum and Rebecca Abraham, 1. ed, 141–46. Guilford, Conn: Dushkin/McGraw-Hill.

    Kornbluh, Anna. 2014. Realizing Capital: Financial and Psychic Economies in Victorian Form. First edition. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Marx, Karl. 2016. Marx’s Economic Manuscript of 1864-1865. Edited by Fred Moseley. Translated by Ben Fowkes. Historical Materialism Book Series 100. Leiden ; Boston: Brill.

    Marx, Karl, and Frederick Engels. 1996. Marx & Engels, Collected Works. Volume 35. Karl Marx – Capital Volume I. Collected Works 35. London: Lawrence & Wishart.

    Marx, Karl, Friedrich Engels, and Manfred Müller. 1992. Gesamtausgabe. Abt. 2. Das Kapital und Vorarbeiten Bd. 4. Ökonomische Manuskripte 1863 – 1867 / Karl Marx Apparat: Teil 2. Vol. 4. Berlin: Dietz.

    Poovey, Mary. 2002. “Writing about Finance in Victorian England: Disclosure and Secrecy in the Culture of Investment.” Victorian Studies 45 (1): 17–41.

    ———. 2008. Genres of the Credit Economy, Mediating Value in Eighteenth- and Nineteenth-Century Britain. University of Chicago Press.

    Saussure, Ferdinand de. 2011. Course in General Linguistics. Edited by Perry Meisel and Haun Saussy. Translated by Wade Baskin. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Taylor, James. 2014. “Financial Crises and the Birth of the Financial Press, 1825-1880.” In The Media and Financial Crises, 203–14. Routledge.

    Weir, David. 1995. Decadence and the Making of Modernism. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press.

    White, Nicholas. 2009. “Introduction.” In Against Nature, by J.-K. Huysmans, translated by Margaret Mauldon, vii–xxvi. Oxford World’s Classics. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press.

    Wilde, Oscar. 2006. The Picture of Dorian Gray. Edited by Joseph Bristow. New ed. Oxford World’s Classics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Ziegler, Robert. 2015. “Huysmans’s Flowers.” Romance Quarterly 62 (1): 50–57. https://doi.org/10.1080/08831157.2015.970115.

    This article is based on parts of my doctoral dissertation. (Gammelgaard 2020)

    [1] White, “Introduction,” xx; in Wilde’s Dorian Gray, the book that so influences Dorian, and which is loosely based on À rebours, is described precisely as a “novel without a plot” (Wilde, The Picture of Dorian Gray, 106).

  • Ryan S. Jeffery–What Are Your Moves Tomorrow

    Ryan S. Jeffery–What Are Your Moves Tomorrow

    This text is published as part of the b2o review‘s “Finance and Fiction” dossier. It can be read as an accompaniment to Ryan S. Jeffery’s ENTER_FACE (8 min. video, 2023).

    What Are Your Moves Tomorrow

    Ryan S. Jeffery

    How to make your way in a world of declining growth?

    One way to understand history is as a struggle between capital and labor. In January 2021 that struggle was eclipsed by a struggle between two types of capital – financial capital and so-called human capital – in the by now infamous GameStop short squeeze. This was the arrival of the meme stock, confidentially, but defiantly, held by Diamond Hands.

    A battle cry in the parlance of emojis, Diamond Hands is internet slang that came to prominence on the subreddit forum r/WallStreetBets. More specifically, it arrived during the global economic shut-down due to the Covid-19 pandemic, when droves of individual, non-professional, so-called “retail” investors banded together to bid up the stock price of the floundering video game retailer GameStop – as well as the movie theater chain AMC. In less than a month GameStop’s stock price went form $17.25 a share to a closing price of $86.88, at a point reaching an all-time high of $500. The result was extraordinary profits for the lucky ones that got in and out early, which simultaneously caused huge losses for so-called institutional investors, i.e. hedge funds who had shorted against the stock.[1]

    It’s this secondary effect that afforded Diamond Hands the ability to see their actions as some form of righteous justice, sticking it to the citadels of Wall Street while finally getting in on some of the action of casino capitalism. This was certainly how the story was broadly told. (Consider, for example, how it’s most recently been depicted in the tepid Hollywood version Dumb Money, a pseudo Big Short part II minus any of Michael Lewis’s trademark smartest people in the room). This populist take pits a David and Goliath scenario in which unruly plebs flew in the face of supposed market fundamentals.[2] In the end, a couple of hedge funds did loose massively – most famously, Melvin Capital shuttered its doors – but other Wall Street players cashed in right behind the wake of chaos created by Diamond Hands. Despite some hand-wringing by financial journalists, the seductive read of a populist revolt was thus short lived: Wall Street’s power remained firmly intact.

    The Diamond Hands short squeeze did succeed, however, in pulling back the curtain, if only for a moment, to reveal just how unwieldy the allocation of value really is within financial capitalism. Unwieldy, if not corrupt: the momentary shutdown of the Robin Hood trading App, which made the short squeeze play possible for traders on the subreddit community, only seemed to confirm just how rigged the game really is. Put simply, it might just come down to the word “bets” in r/WallStreetBets that’s really the greatest provocation to Wall Street insiders who spin narratives of “fundamentals” and “market logics.” Commentator Doug Henwood was even more pointed, noting that despite the fact that these inexperienced traders were using Reddit and the free App Robin Hood, they were really just behaving like any other professional trader: passing information, talking up some stocks and others down. As Henwood argued, what it boiled down to was that simply “the wrong type of people” pulled off such a highly sophisticated Wall Street play.[3]

    Indeed, it didn’t go unnoticed that the aggressive adolescent masculinity found on the r/WallStreetBets message board differs little from the toxic bravado of the rank-and-file on Wall Street. What does separate the professional behind a Bloomberg terminal from the amateur on Robinhood tends to be wealth and power, in other words access to capital, or “liquidity” in the parlance of finance. Short on liquidity, Diamond Hands found their power by organizing and coordinating their numbers through discipline and a perverse sense of solidarity. One retail investor’s paltry position has essentially no effect on market dynamics; if they all pour into a single body, however, then they can become a sizable market actor that other institutional players must contend with. Diamond Hands must act in numbers and they must be committed. In order to act like one: they have to count each other, and also count on each other.

    Described “like 4chan found a Bloomberg terminal,” the entire discourse on r/WallStreetBets is like most anywhere else on the internet, a mix of shit-posting and clever memes but also a genuine exchange of information and a form of community with its own unique vernacular and coded language.[4] The result is an uncanny culture jamming of dominant and overturning media forms that puts the likes of Thanos from the Avengers, Gordon Gekko and Jim Cramer all in one universe. This is the arena in which Diamond Hands emerges. At first appearance, Diamond Hands passes for just another cryptic juvenile insider joke intended just for the lulz, and yet the sophistication of the psychology and utility behind the meme is profound. The challenge is straightforward: the short squeeze play by the r/WallStreetBets traders works only as long as no one sells. So when the stock price begins to move upwards after enough people have bought in, if just a few cash out early, it could spark a wave of selling that would make the whole play collapse. The task is therefore to create an ideology of self-discipline. Diamond Hands relies on the promise—the sacred pact–that you will not sell no matter what, no matter the instability, the incoherence of it all. Your hands are made of diamonds; they will not move no matter which way the price moves. It’s your commitment to holding that’s making the price go up. Once you sell that, everything vanishes. You might not have the cash but you are spiritually rich and linked in this community so long as you keep holding out.

    This is a discipline of equal parts valor and shame, the anti-social sociability of a more perverse Protestant work ethic. But it also reveals how the community of Diamond Hands implicitly understands that they are all atomized and isolated–together. It’s the logic of human capital taken to its conclusion, what Michel Feher has called “investee politics”, a historical shift in the site of capitalist struggle by which individuals no longer look at their labor power as a commodity to sell, but instead view the self as a type of asset that appreciates with particular skills, connections and crucially reputations–all of which either facilitates or bars one’s access to credit-worthiness.[5] It’s a collective vision but without a collective horizon. The struggle is to change their world, not the world. In this light, the GameStop short squeeze play can be understood as Diamond Hands’s recognition that this is likely their only means to reach beyond the precarity of the wage-relation and join the class of capital. In the face of the seemingly immeasurable power of high finance, most will go bankrupt but some might make it through. A nihilistic kamikaze run at the barricades, not necessarily to destroy them but to somehow scale over them. To borrow a phrase: get rich or hold trying.

    In the current configuration of platform capitalism, the original libertarian dream of an emancipatory internet seems naïve, if not delusional. Yet Aris Komporozos-Athanasiou provocatively takes up a more ambivalent position towards both the forms of communication in online spaces as well as the financialized logic that undergirds it. In the face of rapidly accelerating social and political uncertainties, Athanasiou argues that even more radical speculation could act as a pharmakon for the seemingly intractable state of social and political life, wrought by decades of neoliberal reason and digital financialized capitalism. Drawing on Benedict Anderson’s Imagined Communities and the origins of nationalism, Athanasiou describes a new societal formation made up of what he calls speculative communities. Where Anderson looked to the role of print media in the 19th century in the formation of nationalism, Athanasiou sees the current story as one also shaped by media. In this schematic, the “commodified digital infrastructures” of the internet produce speculative technologies be it social media, dating apps, or gig work apps–all built on a high-octane venture capital and so-called creative destruction. The result is the all too familiar experience of modern life reduced to a routine of anxious endless swiping and scrolling in a constant state of competition, precarity, and indebtedness. But counterintuitively, Athanasiou identifies how this increasingly shared experience contains a potential for new forms of collectivity, and in particular collective actions which he calls counter-speculations. Strikingly, these are not moves against the drivers of speculative logic away from uncertainty, but rather its embrace. An accelerationist doubling down of sorts, that only leans harder into uncertainty.

    As he describes it, this is “a speculative politics that does not simply resist the all-encompassing specter of finance but wields it against oppressing structures in all realms of social, political, and even intimate life”.[6] Citing movements as wide-ranging as France’s Gilets Jaunes, the Tea Party, and BLM, along with tactics like divestment campaigns, hashtag-highjacking and Ticktoker pranksterism, Athanasiou claims that what unites them all, is less a concern in resolving the chaos of radical uncertainty. Rather, they are united by an implicit acceptance that this is the precondition for anything different to emerge. In this argument, speculation becomes the means to take action and grasp some form of agency in the face of all-encompassing drowning uncertainty. It’s a logic of fighting fire with fire: speculation got us here, but speculation in the right hands can somehow get us out? Here, r/WallStreetBets’ Diamond Hands falls into sharper relief. From the vantage point of Athanasiou’s speculative communities, the wry cynicism, or even all-out nihilistic juvenility of Diamond Hands, begins to look less like a spectacle in itself, but rather like the spastic response to the already existing spectacles at hand.

    Writing at the time of the GME short squeeze, Max Haiven shrewdly observed how the collective financial play by r/WSB could be understood as a warped version of such explicitly anti-capitalist aims like the Debt Collective, an activist debtor’s union that has collectively organized on behalf of millions of indebted households across the US.[7] Despite r/WSB’s run towards capital as opposed to the Debt Collective’s aim to abolish it, Haiven’s provocative juxtaposition is instructive precisely because of the two groups shared reliance on organizing vast numbers and leveraging structural weak points and contradictions within financial capitalism. This relies on a firm distinction between means and ends. For Haiven, with no unified vision, the “happy accident” of the GME short squeeze urges the question: “What would it mean to leverage the power it revealed towards other ends?”[8]

    On its own, the accomplishment of the GME short squeeze by traders on Reddit offers only a dialectical riddle narrowly within the field of media and culture: is this the financialization of the social or the socialization of finance? But if we widen the lens on this acute moment during the global pandemic to include the split-screen of soaring stock evaluations juxtaposed with precarious worker unrest over who and what is “essential”, deeper questions of politics and agency emerge. Whether an act of action or reaction, the collective market intervention organized on the r/WSB thread reveals innate tensions within networked communications technologies and finance capital, longstanding debates between the so-called real and financial economy, and the very nature of capitalism.

    By January 2024, three years after the GME short squeeze, the share price of the stock was hovering just south of $15, far from the glory of its near $90 high at the height of the short squeeze. Still, it was, and to this day, remains higher than its doomed dollar value just before the Reddit traders of r/WSB intervened in January 2021. Snatched from the predatory jaws of hedge funds, the brick-and-mortar video game retailer can still be found in scattered malls across the world. r/WSB continues on as well, the subreddit currently has fifteen million members, two half million more since the GME short squeeze. Scroll the feed right now and you are less likely to spot the murmurings of such an audacious play than before. What you will find on the thread reads much like a satirical rag about the financial news on any given day. It’s the Financial Times meets the Onion: cleverly decoding and trolling the ideologies spouted by the financial media that are cloaked in the language of objective market signals.

    Perhaps the whole GME affair could simply be chalked up as the freakish byproduct from the reign of Zero-Interest Rate Policy (ZIRP). (The r/WSB short squeeze was of course not the only financial spectacle during the pandemic lockdowns and resulting US monetary interventions, which also saw an accelerated cryptocraze, the rise and fall of NFTs, and continues to roll on in the current speculative wave of so-called generative machine learning technologies.) Michel Feher’s “investee politics” is helpful here in understanding the dynamics between politics and technology, and how they animated the GME affair. For Feher, “the Reddit insurgency” served as evidence that the platform might be supplanting the market as prime mover. He writes: “As coordinators of supply and demand, markets enable profit”, where platforms on the other hand, “play an increasingly important role in the allocation of credit–financial but also moral credit”.[9] The speculative gambit, however seemingly naïve, is to ask how the latter might be leveraged over the former–and crucially towards whose and what moral vision?

    Folding the market into the platform has also long been the vision behind such fintech ventures, going back to the origins of Paypal, Facebook’s failed Libra, and Elon Musk’s current ambitions for X. Silicon Valley is paved with the broken dreams of an “everything app”. But for now, each day the user account u/OPINION_IS_UNPOPULAR pins a version of the same post on top of the r/WSB’s thread: “What Are Your Moves Tomorrow”. Whether the speculative community of r/WSB is a lumpen stratum that can really be mobilized towards a different vision, or the vanguard for a more ruthlessly anarchic market society, remains open.

    Ryan S. Jeffery is a filmmaker and moving image artist. His work focuses on the relation between technology, media and economics.

    [1] See, Davies, Rob. 2021. “GameStop: how Reddit Amateurs took aim at Wall Street short-sellers” The Guardian, January 28. https://www.theguardian.com/business/2021/jan/28/gamestop-how-reddits-amateurs-tripped-wall-streets-short-sellers. See, Stewart, Emily 2021. “The GameStop stock frenzy, explained” Vox, January 29. https://www.vox.com/the-goods/22249458/gamestop-stock-wallstreetbets-reddit-citron.

    [2] See, Winck, Ben. 2021. “GameStop short-sellers lost $1.6 billion in a single day as Reddit traders rebelled against them” Business Insider, January 25. https://markets.businessinsider.com/news/stocks/gamestop-stock-short-seller-squeeze-losses-reddit-traders-citron-gme-2021-1-1030000080. See, Kim, Heejin. 2021. “Michael Burry Calls GameStop Rally ‘Unnatural, Insane’” Bloomberg, January 26. https://www.bloomberg.com/news/articles/2021-01-27/michael-burry-calls-gamestop-gain-unnatural-insane-dangerous?sref=apOkUyd1.

    [3] Henwood, Doug. 2021. “The GameStop Bubble is a Lesson in the Absurdity and Uselessness of the Stock Market” Jacobin Magazine, January 27. https://jacobin.com/2021/01/gamestop-stock-market-reddit.

    [4] See, r/WallStreetBets  https://www.reddit.com/r/wallstreetbets/.

    [5] See Feher, Michel. 2018. Rated Agency: Investee Politics in a Speculative Age. New York: Zone Books.

    [6] Komporozos-Athanasiou, Aris. 2022. Speculative Communities: Living with Uncertainty in a Financialized World. Chicago: Chicago University Press. pg. 11.

    [7] See the Debt Collective https://debtcollective.org.

    [8] Haiven, Max. 2021. “The power, potential and peril of the GameStop affair” Roar Magazine, February 3. https://maxhaiven.com/power-potential-peril/.

    [9] Feher, Michel. 2021. “Another Speculation is Possible: The Political Lesson of r/WallStreetBets” PPE, February 5. https://www.ppesydney.net/another-speculation-is-possible-the-political-lesson-of-r-wallstreetbets/.

  • Ryan S. Jeffery–ENTER_FACE (8 min. video, 2023)

    Ryan S. Jeffery–ENTER_FACE (8 min. video, 2023)

    This video is published as part of the b2o review‘s “Finance and Fiction” dossier. The dossier also includes a text by Ryan S. Jeffery that can be read as an accompaniment to the video.

    Since 1982, the financial data vendor Bloomberg L.P. has provided real-time financial market data accessible only through an interface called the Bloomberg Terminal. For an annual fee of $20,000 you can buy and sell financial assets on Bloomberg’s secure proprietary network with 325,000 other subscribers throughout the world. Since 2012, the user account u/OPINION_IS_UNPOPULAR has moderated the subreddit page r/Wallstreetbets accessible on the public internet forum Reddit, which can be interfaced by web browsing software on most any computer or smartphone. For a zero annual fee you can exchange information, financial trading strategies, videos and memes with 12.9 million other subscribers throughout the world. What would happen if r/Wallstreetbets found a Bloomberg terminal? The interface is where the two systems, subjects, organizations meet and interact.